USF Libraries
USF Digital Collections

Educational policy analysis archives

MISSING IMAGE

Material Information

Title:
Educational policy analysis archives
Physical Description:
Serial
Language:
English
Creator:
Arizona State University
University of South Florida
Publisher:
Arizona State University
University of South Florida.
Place of Publication:
Tempe, Ariz
Tampa, Fla
Publication Date:

Subjects

Subjects / Keywords:
Education -- Research -- Periodicals   ( lcsh )
Genre:
non-fiction   ( marcgt )
serial   ( sobekcm )

Notes

General Note:
Includes EPAA commentary.

Record Information

Source Institution:
University of South Florida Library
Holding Location:
University of South Florida
Rights Management:
All applicable rights reserved by the source institution and holding location.
Resource Identifier:
usfldc doi - E11-00057
usfldc handle - e11.57
System ID:
SFS0024511:00057


This item is only available as the following downloads:


Full Text
xml version 1.0 encoding UTF-8 standalone no
record xmlns http:www.loc.govMARC21slim xmlns:xsi http:www.w3.org2001XMLSchema-instance xsi:schemaLocation http:www.loc.govstandardsmarcxmlschemaMARC21slim.xsd
leader nam a22 u 4500
controlfield tag 008 c19969999azu 000 0 eng d
datafield ind1 8 ind2 024
subfield code a E11-00057
0 245
Educational policy analysis archives.
n Vol. 4, no. 8 (April 21, 1996).
260
Tempe, Ariz. :
b Arizona State University ;
Tampa, Fla. :
University of South Florida.
c April 21, 1996
500
Includes EPAA commentary.
505
Developmentalism : an obscure but pervasive restriction on educational improvement / J.E. Stone.
650
Education
x Research
v Periodicals.
2 710
Arizona State University.
University of South Florida.
1 773
t Education Policy Analysis Archives (EPAA)
4 856
u http://digital.lib.usf.edu/?e11.57



PAGE 1

1 of 32 Education Policy Analysis Archives Volume 4 Number 8April 21, 1996ISSN 10682341A peer-reviewed scholarly electronic journal. Editor: Gene V Glass,Glass@ASU.EDU. College of Educ ation, Arizona State University,Tempe AZ 85287-2411 Copyright 1996, the EDUCATION POLICY ANALYSIS ARCHIVES.Permission is hereby granted to copy any a rticle provided that EDU POLICY ANALYSIS ARCHIVES is credi ted and copies are not sold. Developmentalism: An Obscure but Pervasive Restrict ion on Educational Improvement J. E. StoneEast Tennessee State University STONEJ@EDUSERV.EAST-TENN-ST.EDU Abstract Despite continuing criticism of public education, experimentally demonstrated and field tested teaching methods have been ignored, rejected and abandoned. Instead of a stable consensus regarding best teaching practices, there seems only an unending succession of innovations. A longstanding educational doctrine ap pears to underlie this anomalous state of affairs. Termed developmentalism, it presumes "natu ral" ontogenesis to be optimal and it requires experimentally demonstrated teaching pract ices to overcome a presumption that they interfere with an optimal developmental trajectory. It also discourages teachers and parents from asserting themselves with children. Instead of effe ctive interventions, it seeks the preservation of a postulated natural perfection. Developmentalism's rich history is expressed in a literature extending over 400 years. Its notable exponents inc lude Jean Jacques Rousseau, John Dewey, and Jean Piaget; and its most recent expressions in clude "developmentally appropriate practice" and "constructivism." In the years during which it gained ascendance, developmentalism served as a basis for rejecting harsh and inhumane teachin g methods. Today it impedes efforts to hold schools accountable for student academic achievemen t. Over the past thirteen years American public school s have been subjected to an increasing barrage of criticism. The chief object of complaint has been their continuing failure to equip students with the academic and workplace skills nee ded in an era of increasing economic competition. Recent expressions evidence a growing public impati ence. In an April 1993 statement, U.

PAGE 2

2 of 32S. Secretary of Education Richard Riley commented: "A watered down curriculum and low expectations for too many of our students prevent t hem from meeting high standards" (Riley, 1993). A September 1993 report by the National Cent er for Education Statistics found that 16 to 20 percent of the U. S. adults who perform at the l owest levels of reading, writing, and arithmetic were high school graduates (Kirsch, Jungblut, Jenki ns & Kolstad, 1993). In November of 1993, the U. S. Department of Education reported that in comparison to their peers in other industrialized countries, gifted American students rank near the bottom in math and science achievement (Kantrowitz & Wingert, 1993). In Septem ber of 1994, the American Legislative Exchange Council (ALEC, 1994) disclosed that since the Nation at Risk report in 1983 there has been little change in the achievement levels of pub lic school students despite a 43% increase in real dollar expenditures. Near the end of 1994, the Organization for Economic Co-operation and Development (OECD, 1994) described the quality of A merican education as a major threat to the future economic wellbeing, productivity, and comp etitiveness of the U. S. In April of 1995, Business Week (Mandel, Melcher, Yang & McNamee, 199 5) declared that businesses find too many job applicants unable to read, write, or do si mple arithmetic and that Americans are "fed up" with their public schools. Berliner and Biddle (1995) and various other commen tators (Bracy, 1996; Westbury, 1992) have attempted to defend the public schools' record by offering a more sympathetic interpretation of the available evidence. However, a recent review of Berliner and Biddle (Stedman, 1996a) and the ensuing exchange between B erliner, Biddle and Stedman (Berliner & Biddle, 1996; Stedman, 1996b) demonstrates that rei nterpretation of school and student performance data is unlikely to convince knowledgea ble observers that the ongoing criticisms of public schooling are "manufactured" or otherwise of f target. Despite these mounting concerns, schools have large ly ignored the availability of a number of teaching methodologies that seem capable of prod ucing the kind of achievement outcomes demanded by the public. They are experimentally val idated, field tested, and known to produce significant improvements in learning. Instead, the schools have continued to employ a wide variety of untested and unproven practices which ar e said to be "innovative" (Carnine, 1995; Marshall, 1993). In particular, teaching practices such as mastery learning and Personalized System of Instruction (Bloom, 1976; Guskey & Pigott 1988; Kulik, Kulik & Bangert-Drowns, 1990), direct instruction (Becker & Carnine, 1980; White, 1987), positive reinforcement (Lysakowski & Walberg; 1980, 1981), cues and feedba ck (Lysakowski & Walberg, 1982), and the variety of similar practices called "explicit t eaching" (Rosenshine, 1986), are largely ignored despite reviews and metaanalyses strongly support ive of their effectiveness (Ellson, 1986; Walberg, 1990, 1992). Yet methodologies such as who le language instruction (Stahl & Miller, 1989), the open classroom (Giacomia & Hedges, 1982; Hetzel, Rasher, Butcher, & Walberg, 1980; Madamba, 1981; & Peterson, 1980), inquiry lea rning (ElNemr, 1980), and a variety practices purporting to accommodate teaching to stu dent diversity (Boykin, 1986; Dunn, Beaudrey, & Klavas, 1989; Shipman & Shipman, 1985; Thompson, Entwisle, Alexander, & Sundius, 1992) continue to be employed despite weak or unfavorable findings or simply a lack of empirical trials. Equally surprising is the observation that many of the ignored and rejected methodologies are quite similar to those that have been found eff ective and are routinely used by special educators and school psychologists (Hallahan, Kauff man, & Lloyd, 1985; Hammill & Bartel, 1990; Wang, Reynolds & Walberg, 1987). In many inst ances, the otherwise unused practices are successfully implemented but only after a student h as been identified as disabled. Methods Texts and Experimental Research A sampling of popular textbooks used in regular edu cation teaching methods courses

PAGE 3

3 of 32offers what may be a reason for this anomalous stat e of affairs. Widely used textbooks--in the present report, elementary, middle, and secondary t eaching methods texts that have been revised repeatedly, some over thirty and forty years (Armst rong & Savage, 1994; Callahan, Clark, & Kellough, 1992; Clark & Starr, 1991; Henson, 1993; Jacobsen, Eggen, & Kauchak, 1993; Kim & Kellough, 1995; Lemlech, 1994; Ornstein, 1992; Shep erd & Ragan, 1992)--give little weight to experimentally demonstrated results as a basis for identifying effective teaching practices. Instead, they present an eclectic assortment of app roaches colored by distinct distaste for methods that are structured, teacherdirected, and resultoriented--characteristics that exemplify the experimentally vindicated approaches to teachin g. Lemlech's (1994) account is typical: In classrooms where students are given little oppor tunity to choose what they will learn, how they will learn, a nd the way in which they will be evaluated for learning, there is a greater likelihood that the classroom is structured through intrinsic rewards, incentive programs, and normativ e evaluation. As a consequence, learning will become joyless. There is also a tendency in these classrooms to ove remphasize repetition, drill, and commercially produced dittos for practice materials. Some believe this to be prevale nt in low socio-economic and low achieving classrooms, and as a consequence it may the cause of negative motivation patterns. (p. 91) Instead of empirically grounded recommendations as to best practices, the methods texts suggest a personalized and intuitive approach to in struction built around teacher experience,circumstances, and sensitivity to studen t needs. Ornstein's (1992) advice exemplifies this view: In considering what is best for you, you must consi der your teaching style, your student's needs and abili ties, and your school policies. Asyou narrow your choices remember that approaches overlap and are not mutual ly exclusive. Also remember that more than one approac h may work for you. You may borrow ideas from various approaches and construct your own hybrid. The appro ach you finally arrive at should make sense to you on a n intuitive basis. Don' let someone impose his or her teaching style or disciplinary approach on you. Remember, what works for one person (in the same sc hool, even with the same students) may not work for anoth er person. (p. 129) In essence, these methods texts acknowledge researc h as a foundation for educational practice but give it little weight in formulating a conclusion about the practices most likely to produce results. Neither do they encourage the read er to rely on research as a basis judging the quality of teaching practices. They seem to wear th e mantle of science but oddly neglect its substance and purpose. The same emphasis on teaching shaped by innovation and sensitivity to student differences is quite evident in the catalogues of publishers th at target teachers and teacher educators. The titles and descriptions of offerings by Heinemann ( 1995) and National Education Association (1995), for example, both reflect a market preferen ce for the new and innovative and a market

PAGE 4

4 of 32indifference to the empirically grounded or to the tried and true. The varied and ever-mutating body of scholarship re ferenced by the textbooks implies the kind of ongoing refinement and revitalization chara cteristic of scientifically informed practice. Yet their recommendations with respect to teaching do not reflect the kind of consensus that would be expected to emerge as recent advancements are built onto established findings (Stanovich, 1992, 1993). Empirical findings are at best an imperfect guide to practice; but as they cumulate and converge, they do yield important clue s. At the least, they reveal that certain findings tend to repeat themselves. The impression conveyed by the present textbooks, however, is that learning's relationship to teaching is larg ely idiosyncratic and unpredictable. That which is true for one teacher, teaching one lesson, to one s et of students is not a valid guide for others. Neither do these textbooks acknowledge the unique v alue of experimental trials. The distinctive value of experimental evidence is under stood throughout the scientific community (Cook & Campbell, 1979), and experimentation as a g uide to effective teaching practice has been recognized by the educational community for more th an thirty years (Campbell & Stanley, 1963). Yet the methods texts are silent on the matter. Her e again although the fallibility of empirical evidence must be acknowledged, it must also be said that the well conceived experiment offers more convincing evidence of whether a teaching meth od works than a report offering only description or correlation. Dismissing experimental findings on the grounds that offer only good but not certain evidence of pedagogical effectivene ss is to fallaciously make the perfect the enemy of the good. Given the market success of these textbooks and the teaching profession's apparent comfort with such an orientation, it is not difficu lt to see how schools continue to respond to the public call for better results with untested innova tions (Carnine, 1995). Seemingly the education community has neither a scientifically founded cons ensus about best practices nor a recognition that experimental evidence would be integral to the formation of such a consensus. In the absence of attention to experimental trials, teachi ng innovations lacking demonstrated effectiveness can come into vogue on the strength o f publicity and marketing only to later be bypassed by more of the same (Armstrong, 1980; Carn ine, 1993; Marshall, 1993). In truth, continual innovation may have become a way of copin g with public criticism. New practices are incongruously piled onto the old as consultants, sc hool boards, superintendents, and teachers come and go (Armstrong, 1980). Criticisms that are behind the curve can be ignored because they are no longer relevant. Criticisms of the latest in novations can be ignored because they are premature and intolerant of innovation.The Influence of Developmentalism The thesis advanced in the following is that a long standing but poorly recognized educational doctrine underpins the neglect of exper imental evidence found inmethods textbooks and in the attempt to find more effective teaching methods. It is a doctrine that pervades teacher education and one that disposes the teaching profes sion to favor certain practices and to ignore others regardless of empirically demonstrated merit Termed "developmentalism" (Stone, 1991, 1993a, 1994), it is a form of romantic naturalism t hat inspires teacher discomfort with any practice that is deemed incompatible with natural d evelopmental processes (Binder & Watkins, 1989). It is a view that acquired popularity as a g rounds for rejecting the often harsh formalist teaching methods of the eighteenth and nineteenth c enturies (Ravitch, 1983; Riegel, 1972). Today it poses an obscure but powerful restriction on scientifically informed educational improvement and more broadly on teacher and parent efforts to influence the developing child. Developmentalism's clearest present-day expressions include the "child centered" or "progressive" teaching seen in Canadian schools (Fr eedman, 1993), the "progressivism" or "Plowdenism" seen in the British Primary Schools (A lexander, Rose, & Woodhead, 1992), and

PAGE 5

5 of 32the "developmentally appropriate practice" advocate d by early childhood educators (Carta, Schwartz, Atwater & McConnell,1991). The learner-ce ntered teacher education favored by National Education Association is another expressio n, one that is widely known and well regarded in colleges of education (Darling-Hammond, Griffin & Wise, 1992). Discovery learning is predicated on developmentalis m (Bruner, 1966) and so is the increasingly popular constructivism (Brooks & Brook s, 1993). Although constructivism employs a distinctive terminology and a more credible theor etical foundation, its major precepts are largely those advanced by John Dewey (1916/1963) at the turn of the century and discredited in the nineteen fifties. Dewey's "progressive educatio n" (Dewey, 1938/1963) is the best known historic form of developmentalism and one whose pre sent day influence is remarkably underestimated. "Reflective thinking," "authentic l earning," "hands-on" experiences, "authentic assessment," and many other of today's best known p edagogical terms and concepts are rooted in Dewey's adaptation of developmentalism. Other recen t (but now less popular) forms of developmentalism are the "third force" and "humanis tic" psychologies on which the educational innovations of the nineteen sixties and seventies w ere based (Weber, 1972). A variety of other popular practices are less expli citly developmentalist but they share developmentalism's premises about the goodness of t he natural--a characteristic that is key to their acceptance by the educational mainstream. Wel l known examples include the "whole language" and "language experience" approaches to r eading (Altwerger, Edelsky & Flores, 1987), the closely related "emergent literacy" view of rea ding (Teal & Sulzby, 1987), and the "cognitive apprenticeship" approach to instruction (Brown, Col lins, and Duguid, 1989). Stahl and Miller's (1989) discussion of whole language and language ex perience reading instruction highlights its appeal as a "natural" mode of instruction: "The goa l of both approaches is to bring children into literacy in a 'natural' way [italics added], by bri dging the gap between children's own language competencies and written language" (p. 88).Developmentalism: The Term and Its Referents Although Stone (1991, 1993a, 1994) seems to have or iginated the use of "developmentalism" in reference to the doctrine dis cussed herein, similar terms have been used to denote developmentally informed educational prac tice. Sprinthall and Sprinthall (1987) used the term "developmentalists" in reference to educat ors who base their practices on developmental considerations. A similar term-"philosophic-devel opmentalist"-was used by Lawrence Kohlberg and Rochelle Mayer (1972) in reference to the views of John Dewey (1859-1952) and Jean Piaget (1896-1980). Dewey's and Piaget's views were termed "interactionist" and those of Jean Jacques Rousseau (1712-1778), "maturationist." In contrast to these precedents, developmentalism as used by Stone (1991, 1993a, 199 4) refers to a broad doctrine that presumes "natural" ontogenesis to be optimal. Such a presump tion is common to both maturationist and interactionist views of development; and it is impl icit in Dewey, Piaget, Rousseau, and the others here termed developmentalists. As the term is used here, the "ism" in developmentalism is the uncontested assumption that the "natural" course of development, however conceived in theory, is the optimal possibility. It is an obscure but vi tal form of romantic naturalism--one thoroughly embedded in the American culture. Stated broadly, developmentalism is the view of age related social, emotional, and cognitive change that regards the optimal progressi on to be a fragile result of native tendencies emerging in a world congenial to their presumed who lesome nature. It emphasizes (a) the sufficiency of a natural inclination to learning, ( b) the dangers of interference with native characteristics and proclivities, and (c) the desir ability of learning experiences that emulate those thought to occur naturally. Social, emotional, and cognitive attributes that may be the unrecognized result of teacher and parent intervent ion are presumed by developmentalism to be

PAGE 6

6 of 32manifestations of nature's normal trajectory. Man, his social contrivances, and indeed, civilization are seen as distinct from nature; and deliberate efforts to alter the course of child development are suspected of interfering with optim al developmental outcomes. Developmentalism assumes that the developmental dir ections issuing from the child's native tendencies and characteristics are optimal b ecause they are a part of "nature." Although their concepts of development differed, Rousseau, D ewey, Piaget, and all other developmentalists share this premise. For Rousseau, nature was God's work untainted by human influence. In his view, the optimal developmental p rogression was simply the emergence of native tendencies and characteristics unfettered an d unspoiled by society. By contrast, Dewey and Piaget considered the child's tendencies and charac teristics to be the product of Darwinian evolution. Native tendencies and characteristics we re desirable because they had survived the process of natural selection. Unlike Rousseau, Dewe y and Piaget held that the optimal progression depended not only on successful maturat ion but on a natural process of interaction wherein the native characteristics selected-for by evolution were enhanced by the naturally occurring experiences to which they were fitted (Ko hlberg & Mayer, 1972). Thus originated Dewey's emphasis on authentic educational experienc e. Evolution equipped humans to learn by solving problems, therefore learning in the context of problem solving was optimal. Although Rousseau's development was more exclusively a matte r of maturation, he too treated social and educational influences as having the ability to eit her facilitate and nurture, or to corrupt and misdirect the optimal progression to which nature w as postulated to tend. A Brief History of Developmentalism Developmentalism's historic foundations go well bey ond the writings of Rousseau, Dewey, and Piaget. Pedagogical theorists such as Johann Be rnard Basedow (1724-1790), Johann Heinrich Pestalozzi (1746-1827), Georg Wilhelm Frie drich Hegel (1770-1831), Friedrich Froebel (1782-1852), Herbert Spencer (1820-1903), William J ames (1842-1910), and G. Stanley Hall (1844-1924) are the best known proponents of the pa st 200 years. In general, their views were premised on either the maturation-only or the matur ation/environmentalinteraction schemes of development. The ascendance of developmentalism in America may b e related to an early belief about education as a cause of madness. According to Makar i (1993), Rousseau's "education naturelle" was presaged by the writings of John Locke in 1691 and Giambattista Vico in 1709. Vico believed that children develop through a series of immutable phases and he condemned educational practices not in harmony with the "natu ral" progression. He considered abstract Cartesian thought to be particularly harmful. Vico' s supposition that that which appears to be unnatural is apt to harmful has been echoed repeate dly even to the present day. Proponents of "developmentally appropriate" teaching practice, fo r example, believe that the use of incentives with young children are likely to be damaging. Vico's belief was accepted within American psychiat ry from its earliest years, and it persisted in the professional literature well into the late eighteen hundreds (Makari, 1993). The public and professional acceptance of such thinking as enlightened and informed clearly would have lent credibility to the criticisms of formalis t teaching methods voiced by Dewey, James, and others. Also it would have bolstered the acceptance of the developmentalist schooling methods imported from Europe throughout the era.Rousseau and European Developmentalists Rousseau argued that all that comes from the hand o f the Creator must be good; and in

PAGE 7

7 of 32doing so, he substituted a doctrine of original goo dness for that of original sin. He believed that formal schooling was not only unnecessary (because children tend naturally to learn) but that it harms students by violating their natural propensit ies (Green, 1955). Classically premised on a romanticist faith in nature, Rousseau's Emile was a critique of educational practice in his day. Hegel embellished Rousseau's theme and described ch ild development as a process of unfoldment toward a state of natural perfection (Bi gge & Hunt, 1962). Basedow, Pestalozzi, and Froebel each articulated their unique vision of sch ooling based on Rousseau's and Hegel's concepts (Rusk, 1965). In each case, their conceptu al framework required schooling to be fitted to the child in the interest of preserving the good ness inherent in nature, and in each case they were received by the European public as a welcome a lternative to the often harsh teaching methods of the day. Teachers of the era typically w ere retired drill sergeants and their methods were adaptations of military training (Riegel, 1972 ). Herbert Spencer and William James Spencer and James similarly argued that education m ust be fitted to the child but their ideas were premised on an evolutionary model of nat ure (Cremin, 1964). The vision of natural perfection suggested by evolutionary theory differe d from that of Rousseau but the ideal of education in harmony with natural perfection again was perpetuated. Optimal educational results were those that arose from fulfillment of nature's inherent order--an order shaped by the workings of evolution. Although Spencer and James both relie d on an evolutionary premise, their thinking diverged as to the relationship between the natural order and desirable educational outcomes. Spencer conceived of education as subordinate to an d, ideally, accommodated to the broader evolutionary process. He held that men were "infini tely more creatures of history than its creators" (Cremin, 1964, p. 93). Thus educational p ractice fitted to nature's dictates was the arrangement most conducive to optimal enhancement o f the species. In contrast, James conceived of the human mind as having an active rol e in shaping the natural order and; more than Spencer, Rousseau, or Dewey, he believed that teach ers should instill good (i.e., adaptive) habits. James differed in other important ways from Dewey a nd other developmentalists. In contrast to Dewey, James conceived of educational o utcomes as specific observable behavior change, not as a broad gaged and intangible intelle ctual growth. Also in contrast to Dewey and most other developmentalists, James believed that l earned habits could serve to inhibit or overcome unfavorable natural tendencies. Thus he wa s he was not especially critical of recitation and the older "formalist" educational methods, and neither did he expect all learning to be motivated by a genuine personal interest. In James' s words, the belief that learning should be motivated only by interest was "soft pedagogy" (Jam es, 1899/1924, p. 109). As to the relationship between human development an d learning, James held that evolution had endowed humans with naturally "ripening" instin cts and native interests to which successful teaching should be fitted. Unlike Dewey and other d evelopmentally informed theorists, however, he did not insist on adherence to nature's ripening process or on an approximation of nature's interaction patterns as the optimal means of educat ing. Rather James' Talks to Teachers (1899/1924) offered practical recommendations that could be implemented largely without reference to developmental considerations. Thus in spite of his attention to human development as an educational consideration, James, unlike Dewe y, did not greatly contribute to the restrictive orthodoxy that is developmentalism.G. Stanley Hall and Arnold Gesell G. Stanley Hall may have been the individual most r esponsible for infusing the American educational tradition with the maturation-only vers ion of developmentalism (Strickland &

PAGE 8

8 of 32Burgess, 1965). Hall believed that quality teaching was that which was fitted to what he termed a "saltatory" pattern of development--a pattern he be lieved to have been dictated by human evolutionary history (Hall, 1907). Hall's views are among the most explicitly developm entalist in the history of American education; and although his "general psychonomic la w" (ontogeny recapitulates phylogeny) was eventually rejected, his concept of improving the e ducational process through the study of child development became a mainstay educational orthodoxy (McCullers, 1969). In his essay "The Ideal School as Based on Child Study," Hall argued that contrary to accepted Western educational practice, the school should be fitted t o the child rather than the child fitted to the school. Teachers, he believed, . should strive first of all to keep out of nat ure's way, and to prevent harm, and should merit the prou d title of defenders of the rights and happiness of children. They should feel profoundly that childhoo d, as it comes fresh from the hand of God, is not corr upt, but illustrates the survival of the most consummate thing in the world; they should be convinced that t here is nothing else so worthy of love, reverence, and service as the body and soul of the growing child. (cited in Cremin, 1964, p. 103). In his definitive account of progressive education, Cremin (1964, p. 104) argues that the popularization of Hall's "pediocentric" view was "t ruly Copernician" because it shifted the "burden of proof" for learning from the student to the school. Coming at a time when compulsory education was becoming widespread, its impact on Am erican education was enormous and continues to be felt. The aim of improving the educational process throug h child study was further popularized by Hall's student Arnold Gesell. Although not widel y read today, Gesell's developmental concepts are consistent with popularly held views o f early childhood development (cited in Bigge & Hunt, 1962): As with a plant, so with a child. His mind grows by natural stages. A child creeps before he walks, sit s before he stands, cries before he laughs, babbles b efore he talks, draws a circle before he draws a square, lies before he tells the truth, and is selfish before he is altruistic. Such sequences are part of the order of Nature. . Every child, therefore, has a unique pattern of growth, but that pattern is a variant of a basic ground plan. (p. 166) John Dewey and Progressive Education John Dewey is another developmentalist who did not rely on a formally stated developmental sequence. Instead, Dewey believed tha t evolution had equipped man with characteristics fitted to certain types of naturall y occurring experiences and that the learning that emerges as the individual encounters these experien ces is optimal. Quality teaching was, therefore, the practice of fitting educational expe riences to the emerging characteristics and proclivities of the child for the purpose of optimi zing "growth." Optimal development was both

PAGE 9

9 of 32driven by maturation and nurtured by experience. In contrast to Rousseau, Dewey did not consider maturation sufficient to guide the process Instead, he was frequently critical of progressive educators who followed Rousseau's matur ational precepts, referring to their . idealizing of childhood [as] . lazy indulgence" (cited in Axtelle & Burnette, 1970, p. 260). Also contrary to popular belief, Dewey conceived of school as a structured experience in which teachers would ingeniously arrange student en counters with personally meaningful problems--problems which, if well chosen, would ins tigate self-directed learning experiences (Dewey, 1916/1963). The teacher's actions, however, were intended as a means of facilitating or enhancing a spontaneous learning process, not as a means of unnaturally or artificially inducing a preconceived outcome. In Dewey's words, the only pr oper aim of education is "growth" (Dewey, 1916/1963): Since growth is the characteristic of life, educati on is all one with growing; it has no end beyond itself. The criterion of the value of school education is the e xtent in which it creates a desire for continued growth a nd supplies means for making the desire effective in f act. (p. 53) Dewey argued that the right sort of experience woul d instigate "reflective" thinking and thereby move the student toward a meaningful and in dividually defined form of knowing. The problem solving experience was, in his view, nature 's way of teaching--the way in which the species had been equipped for learning by virtue of natural selection. Dewey's prescriptions for teaching were designed to emulate nature's process. Because he believed that true understanding was per sonalized, Dewey held that educational aims could not be dictated by any agent external to the student (Dewey, 1916/1963, 1938/1963; Feldman, 1934/1968). For this reason, De wey's concepts severely limited the ability of teachers to insure that students acquire any pre conceived understanding or knowledge. Education was a process intended to enhance the stu dent's reflective powers. That subject-matter which a student learned incidental to the education al process was the only important or expected kind of formal educational achievement--a view clea rly at odds with traditional expectations for schooling and with the concept of teacher accountab ility for specific academic accomplishments. An individual's familiarity with the knowledge and insights gleaned by intellectual forebearers was of secondary importance in Dewey's thinking. Dewey's departure from traditional expectations for schooling was tied to his reliance on an evolutionary model of nature (Boydston, 1970). H e believed that progressive schooling would produce varied outcomes; that the outcomes most adv antageous to society would be selected for; and that society would be bettered by the process. Although he opposed preconceived outcomes as the aim of schooling, his faith in human rationa lity led him to expect that students would arrive at commonly held truths as a result of their personal explorations. A similarly founded departure from conventional exp ectations for schooling--Dewey's emphasis on student interest as the sole legitimate source of student motivation-led to practical difficulties with his approach. Because student int erests might be far removed from conventional academic pursuits, the time, effort, and resources necessary to elicit their emergence was destined to collide with economic reality. The cost-effectiv eness of schooling was not a major consideration in Dewey's time. Neither was the avai lability of meaningful occupational opportunities for students whose natural thirst for learning was significantly delayed. Thus in spite of his pragmatic orientation, neither Dewey n or his followers seemed to appreciate the pedagogic and economic inefficiencies that would re sult as growing children became immersed in a world increasingly dominated by competing attr actions. As to reliance on formal knowledge of human develop ment, Dewey called for teachers to

PAGE 10

10 of 32be guided by the emergence of the individual studen t but to be informed by known developmental considerations (1916/1963): The method of [knowing and learning exhibited by an individual student] . will vary from that of an other (and properly vary) as his original instinctive capacities vary, as his past experiences and his preferences vary. Those who have already studied th ese matters are in possession of information which will help teachers in understanding the responses different p upils make, and help them in guiding these responses to greater efficiency. Child-study, psychology, and a knowledge of the social environment supplement the personal acquaintance gained by the teacher. But methods remain the personal concern, approach, and attack of an individual, and no catalogue can ever exhaust their diversity of form and tint. (p. 173) In essence, the student's "needs" were to guide the selection and sequencing of educational experiences. Accordingly, Dewey's curriculum was co mprised of the subject matter and experiences that fit the unique pursuits of the ind ividual. Knowledge of formal subject matter was purely incidental to the educational process (D ewey, 1938/1963). The fact of Dewey's long and prestigious career com bined with the extensive influence of the progressive education movement resulted in Dewe y's principles and its inherent developmentalism becoming a very potent educational orthodoxy. Cremin (1964) notes that by the late nineteen forties and early fifties, the la nguage and concepts of progressive education were no longer thought of as representing a particu lar educational view. Rather they were simply considered good and sensible educational practice. For a period of fifty or so years following World War I, both the U. S. Office of Education and the National Education Association disseminated educational recommendations based on p rogressive principles as "best practices." Today, teaching practices inspired by Dewey's conce pts continue to attract adherents despite discouraging empirical findings. The attempt to imp rove student achievement by matching teaching styles with learning styles and investigat ions of attributetreatment interactions are examples of research that fail to support Dewey's r ecommendations for teaching (Slavin, 1991). Within teacher education, progressivists were extre mely influential. William Heard Kilpatrick held the senior chair in social foundati ons of education at Teachers College, Columbia University from 1918 to 1938. During that time he i s said to have taught 35,000 teachers (Cremin, 1964). Thus even though progressive educat ion per se eventually fell into disrepute, its concepts and jargon were so thoroughly established as "conventional wisdom" that the reasonableness and intuitive appeal of all subseque nt educational theorizing was largely governed by its compatibility with progressive conc epts--concepts that for the most part embodied one or another version of developmentalism Neoprogressive Theorists Subsequent to progressive education's demise in the late nineteen fifties, a number of neoprogressive psychological theories, all possessi ng a strong developmentalist bent, gained widespread popularity within the teaching professio n (Weber, 1972). Exemplars include Lawrence Frank, Daniel Prescott, Carl Rogers, Arthu r Combs, Abraham Maslow, A. S. Neill,

PAGE 11

11 of 32and Erik Erickson--all of whom viewed central aim o f education as a broad gauged personal development. Although their theoretical foundations and emphases diverged from those of progressive education, (for example, the liberation of human potential, the enhancement of self-esteem, the achievement of self-actualization, etc.), their recommendations for teachers were plainly congruent with progressive education's focu s on facilitation of naturally developing tendencies and processes. Other theorists emphasize d narrower facets of development but they too were entirely compatible with developmentalism and progressive education (Weber, 1972). These include Paul Torrence who focused on the deve lopment of intellectual creativity and Lawrence Kohlberg who articulated a moral developme nt progression based on Piaget's general framework. Of particular relevance to present day educational practice are the neoprogressive accounts of cognitive development that became popular in the late nineteen sixties and early seventies. Jerome Bruner and, especially, Jean Piaget are the best known exemplars in this area; and both are essentially compatible with Dewey, particularly in their emphasis of a natural, i.e., personal discovery, type of learning experience.Jean Piaget and Lev Vygotsky As earlier noted, Kohlberg and Mayer (1972) identif ied both Piaget and Dewey as exponents of "philosophicdevelopmentalism"--a vie w that holds intellectual growth to be the only defensible aim of education. Piaget's theory w as grounded in his extensive observations of his three children and in a host of more systematic investigations undertaken subsequently. By training a biologist, Piaget described what seemed to be a biologically shaped sequence of person/ environment interaction--one he believed ne cessary to the emergence of individual intelligence. Thus, in contrast to the commonsensic al and anecdotal accounts of intellectual development offered by Dewey, Piaget's work provide d educators an elaborate theoretical edifice based on legitimate scientific observation. The Russian psychologist Vygotsky (1987), a contemp orary of Piaget, similarly conceived of a biologically shaped developmental progression but with an important differences in emphasis. In contrast to Piaget, Vygotsky argued th at learning as a result of sociocultural experiences played a far greater role in the emerge nce of mature thinking and behavior. The influence of experience on behavior, however, was l imited by a biologically governed zone of proximal development. Of the two theorists, Piaget was far better known and thus exerted far greater influence on educational practice. Given the credibility of his findings, Piaget's edu cational recommendations were taken as substantially more authoritative and convincing tha n those of Rousseau, Dewey, and the others. Yet, despite its merits, Piaget's theorizing did no t escape the preconceptions of its predecessors. As had Dewey and Rousseau, Piaget surveyed that whi ch he took to be the naturally occurring developmental progression and presumed it optimal. Thus his conclusions--ones buttressed by impressive theoretical and empirical refinements-conferred a predictable and welcome affirmation of developmentalist beliefs. Piaget's educational recommendations were intended to preserve "natural" experiences and to facilitate that which is unique to the individua l. According to Kohlberg and Mayer (1972) they include: . (1) attention to the child's mode or style o f thought, i.e., stage; (2) match of stimulation to t hat stage, e.g., exposure to modes of reasoning one sta ge above the child's own; (3) arousal, among children, of genuine cognitive and social conflict and disagreem ent

PAGE 12

12 of 32 about problematic situations (in contrast to tradit ional education which has stressed adult "right answers" and has reinforced "behaving well"); and (4) exposure t o stimuli toward which the child can be active, in wh ich assimilatory response to the stimulus-situation is associated with "natural" feedback. (p. 462 ) Although the empirical underpinnings of Piaget's fr amework have been undermined by subsequent research (Siegler, 1991) and his theory significantly revised (Case, 1991), Piaget's thinking remains highly influential with mainstream educators. Its recent educational expression is the increasingly well known "constructivism" (Br ooks & Brooks, 1993); and as with virtually all popular educational doctrines, its acceptance b y the educational mainstream reflects its compatibility with Dewey and developmentalism. Over ton (1972) acknowledges the mutually supportive relationship between Piagetian developme ntal concepts and Dewey. In essence, Dewey enabled popularization of Piaget, and Piaget has provided a seemingly unassailable rationale for Dewey's educational prescriptions: . Piaget's functional position contributes primarily to educational foundations and methods. T he implications of his major emphasis upon activity ec ho progressive education's assertions of intrinsic motivation, self-direction, and freedom of the lear ner. The detailed analysis of the nature of the activiti es involved in adaptation stresses the significance of discovery-oriented methods in which the teacher act ively participates by presenting appropriate materials an d setting appropriate problems over methods of rote d rill, training, or enriched environments. Above all, ther e is the point shared with progressive education that learning and development occur through the experien ce of the child's actively confronting his social and phy sical world. (Overton, 1972, p. 113-114) Thus the theoretical and empirical expressions of p resent day (mainly Piagetian) developmentalism may not be Dewey's but its conclus ions about educational practice are largely the same (Reschly & Sabers, 1974). Although today viewed principally as guide to teach ing at the primary school level, developmentalism serves as a conceptual foundation for educational practice at all levels (Clark & Starr, 1991; Sprinthall & Sprinthall, 1987; Squir e, 1972; Wlodkowski, 1986). At the preschool and K-3 levels, the "developmentally appropriate in struction" concept has so thoroughly penetrated educational thinking that it is included in the "America 2000" statement of national educational goals (U.S. Department of Education [US DOE], 1991); it is acknowledged in the school reform principles formulated by business lea ders (Committee for Economic Development, 1991); and it is explicitly cited in school reform legislation (Kentucky Education Reform Act, 1990; Stone, 1993).Developmentalism's Restrictions on Teaching and Par enting Developmentalism's effect on educational reform mus t be understood in the context of its influence on teaching, parenting, and socialization as a whole. As the now popular African

PAGE 13

13 of 32proverb suggests, "it takes a village to raise a ch ild," thus the influence developmentalism's strictures and recommendations on the actions of bo th parents and teachers are critical to schooling outcomes. In general, developmentalist guidance has encourage d parents and teachers to be less assertive and to afford children greater freedom. I n particular, it has encouraged lessened parent insistence on study and effort in school and on mat ure and responsible behavior generally. Parents are given to believe that in a developmenta lly accommodative world, frustration and delayed gratification are to be minimized while imm ediate success and satisfaction are to be maximized. For example, an NEA publication by Wlodk owski (1986), discourages teachers' from insisting on results: We need to look more at the process and performance of our students and less at the more narrow and selfdefeating emphasis of product or acquisition. If a student is responding with enthusiasm and interest, she/he will probably learn, but often without a nea t, continuous, daily progress line. To lose our studen ts' excitement and involvement for lack of immediate learning is not only a waste of effort but also a d anger to the ultimate goal of any teacher--a student who is on the road to becoming a lifelong learner. (p. 16) The National Association for the Education of Young Children (NAEYC) is more specific. Its policy statement on "developmentally appropriat e practice" identifies that the following actions to be inappropriate (Bredekamp, 1988): The teacher's role is to correct errors and make su re the child knows the right answer in all subject are as. Teachers reward children for correct answers with stickers or privileges, praise them in front of the group, and hold them up as examples. (p. 76) Broadly speaking, developmentalism and its restrict ions on teaching practice argue against intervention and, instead, favor the kind of premis siveness found in the child-rearing recommendations of Dr. Benjamin Spock (1976) and ot hers (Brazelton, 1974; Gessell & Ilg, 1943; Warner & Rosenberg, 1976). In truth, Spock, e t al and the educational developmentalists rely on many of the same theoretical foundations. Developmentalism suggests that both teacher and par ent expectations for behavior or achievement must be subordinated to concerns about optimal development. Rather than seek to shape the child to social or academic norms, develo pmentally informed teachers and parents are deemed responsible for affording experiences and op portunities that are compatible with the child's current proclivities. That such experiences will result in effort and achievement commensurate with individual potential is simply ta ken for granted. Clark and Starr (1991, p.37) exemplify this view in their textbook on secondary and middle school teaching methods: "Because learning is developmental, it follows that one learns better when one is ready to learn." Bigge and Hunt's (1962, p. 377) text is more explic it: "A young person is ready to learn something when he has achieved sufficient physiolog ical maturation and experiential background so that he not only can learn but wants to." Whatever the measurable impact of developmentally i nformed teaching and parenting on the course of child development (a remarkably littl e examined topic), its immediate impact on teacher and parent attempts to instruct and discipl ine are entirely foreseeable. Developmentalism

PAGE 14

14 of 32gives rise to a disabling hesitancy and uncertainty about how or whether adults should attempt to influence children. It strongly suggests the possib ility of harm, but it offers no clear guidance as to a safe and effective course of action. It requir es an estimation of a child's developmental status as a prerequisite to action yet it offers no workab le means of ascertaining that status. The requirement of correctly inferring individual d evelopment presents a substantial obstacle to the application of developmental theory The prototypic studies of human development by Gessell (1940, 1943, 1946), Gesell, Ilg, and Ames (1956), and McGraw (1945/1969) tracked physical and motor development-both low inference constructs. The indicators of development--height, weight, number o f teeth, number of steps, etc.--were visible and readily quantifiable. By contrast, the phases o f social, emotional, and cognitive development to which developmentally appropriate teaching and p arenting must be fitted are high inference constructs, i.e., ones said to be manifested by com plex patterns of behavior. The inherent observational problem is evident in Piaget's concep t of intelligence (Furth & Wachs, 1975): For Piaget, intelligence is constructive and creati ve; in fact, development of intelligence is but the gra dual creation of new mechanisms of thinking. It is creat ion because it is not the discovery or the copy of anyt hing that is physically present. Classes and probability cannot be found in the physical world. They are concepts constructed creatively by human intelligen ce and cannot be handed down by means of language or o ther symbols. (pp. 25-26) To add to the imprecision and uncertainty of the re quired inference, Piaget's theory holds that the relationship between current behavior and developmental status is neither fixed nor self-evident and that the underlying developmental progression is characterized by spurts, lulls, and uneven dispersion across the various behavioral emotional, and intellectual domains. Again in reference to Piaget (Furth & Wachs, 1975): This variability takes three forms, each of which i s contrary to a normative ideal. First, different individuals differ on the same task and much more t han an IQ mentality would have us believe. . A seco nd type of variability is found within a certain indiv idual (intraindividual variability) as he performs on a variety of different tasks [tasks requiring the sam e underlying intellectual capability]. . A third type of variability is observed both within the same individual and on the same task. In other words, th e performance of a child fluctuates from day to day-an entirely normal phenomenon that all of us experienc e. . Recognition and acceptance of this variability is particularly important in the case of mechanisms of thinking which develop gradually and almost imperceptibly [italics added]. (pp. 28-29) In addition to their ambiguity, estimates of develo pmental status are inherently conservative and restrictive of adult action. Conce ptually, current levels of intellectual performance, effort, maturity, achievement, and oth er indicators can understate but not exceed present levels of development. For example, a child whose reasoning is concrete operational may

PAGE 15

15 of 32exhibit skills indicative of the earlier preoperati onal level but they would never misleadingly exhibit skills appropriate to the more mature forma l operations level. Thus assessments of development based on a child's current behavior may underestimate but not overestimate present developmental status. Given that developmentally appropriate teaching and parenting must be fitted to the child's current developmental status, and given that effort s to exhort or otherwise induce advancement beyond the child's developmentally governed potenti alities are considered risky at best, teachers and parents are given to understand that expecting too little is a much better choice than expecting too much. From a developmentalist perspec tive, if opportunity and conditions conducive to developmental advancement have been ma ximized, the developmentally guided teacher or parent has done all that can safely be d one. In effect, developmentalism discourages teachers an d parents from asserting expectations or otherwise acting to induce more mature behavior. Even in the face of noticeable deficiencies or problematic conduct, the developmentally appropr iate course of action is that which is congenial to the child's apparent developmental sta tus, i.e., his or her present behavior and inclinations. Continuing lack of advancement in spi te of suitable facilitating conditions is taken to reflect delayed emergence of developmentally gov erned potentialities, not ineffective teaching or parenting.Personal, Social, and Cultural Implications The implications of such a perspective are far-reac hing and they may be relevant to the well known concerns about the waning influence of h omes and schools. In a world that affords few immediate incentives for responsible and constr uctive behavior, children whose teachers and parents are captivated by developmentalism may be s ignificantly disadvantaged: They are too little influenced by those adults who have the grea test interest in their well being. To the extent that teachers, parents, and other socially ordained influences are withheld, "default contingencies" (John Eshleman, personal communicati on, February 26, 1993)-i.e., influences arranged by peers, by the entertainment and recreat ion industries, etc.--are empowered. Not only does developmentalism appear to undermine teacher and parent assertiveness, the view of children inherent in developmentalism may b e negatively linked to the "growth" of maturity, character, and a sense of personal respon sibility. Rather than encouraging parents to treat children and youth as individuals responsible for their own behavior, developmentalism encourages tolerance and acceptance of immaturity, irresponsibility, and failure. And given the belief that mature and responsible behavior simply emerges if properly facilitated, the child who fails to exhibit expected social and academic progr ess is excused as a victim of adverse circumstances--a rationale for individual shortcomi ngs that has become a cultural archetype (Birnbaum, 1991). The influence of developmentalism and its philosoph ic foundation, romantic naturalism, may extend far beyond teaching and parenting practi ces. For example, the growth of so called "anti-science" (Holton, 1993; Kurtz, 1993) and of c ertain forms of environmentalism seem to be linked to the same romantic assumptions about the w holesomeness of nature that are integral to developmentalism. Over a 75 year period development alism has been a prominent feature of educational practice, and from this venue, it has h ad opportunity to thoroughly infuse the American culture. The degree to which popular thoug ht in America may have been influenced by romanticist leanings within the public schools, how ever, is well beyond the present analysis. Implications for Schoolwork Learning of the kind sought by schools inevitably r equires very substantial commitments

PAGE 16

16 of 32of student time and effort (Tomlinson, 1992). Devel opmentalism, however, discourages teachers from any attempt to directly induce it. Instead, de velopmentalism requires that teachers endeavor to produce "learning in ways that are stimulating y et minimally obtrusive, challenging yet requiring only comfortable levels of exertion" (Sto ne, 1994, p. 65). An anomaly becomes apparent (Stone, 1994): . schools [are encouraged] to spare neither ef fort nor resources in fitting instruction to students wh ile expecting little from them in return. Student inattention and apathy are met with herculean effor ts to stimulate interest and enthusiasm. Deficient outcom es are countered by reducing expectations to the level of whatever the student seems willing to do. Even the practice of [motivating students by] affording . accurate feedback about accomplishments is deemed questionable because of its purported detrimental e ffect on intrinsic motivation and self esteem. . recurrent failure to attain even minimal achievement is accepted as lamentable but unavoidab le and treated accordingly. In short, developmentalism requires only the teacher to work, not the student. (p. 62) In essence, developmentalism leads to schools in wh ich attendance is compulsory but study is not. Students are expected to make an effo rt only if they feel interested and enthused. Study is expected to be more like fun than work. If students waste time and educational opportunity because they find schoolwork boring, th eir behavior is not merely tolerated, it is understood and excused as the product of insufficie ntly stimulating instruction, i.e., instruction that fails to facilitate the emergence of the postu lated ideal. In the end, teachers are burdened with an unattaina ble expectation. They, their employers, and the public are encouraged to believe that if a teacher is sufficiently creative and ingenious in harnessing each individual student's potentialities expected learning outcomes will emerge in a way that the student will experience as spontaneous natural, and comfortable. It is an ideal founded wholly on developmentalist supposition but it has come to define good teaching. Developmentalism's ideal of taking the work out of schoolwork may be responsible not only for poor work habits and attitudes beyond the classroom--a problem widely noted by employers (Mandel, Melcher, Yang & McNamee, 1995; S urvey, 1991). So long as study and effort are expected only if the student feels so in clined, the self discipline necessary to putting school "work before pleasure" is largely omitted fr om the academic regimen. Instead of a work ethic, students are given to expect significant acc omplishments with minimal effort (Shine, 1993).Educationally Appropriate Practice A vital distinction must be drawn between developme ntally appropriate instruction and educationally appropriate instruction, i.e., those teaching practices that accommodate teaching to the learner without regard to the hypothetical cons traints posed by developmental theory. Developmentally appropriate instruction (a.k.a. dev elopmentally appropriate practice) seeks to optimize the development of the "whole child" (John son & Johnson, 1992) irrespective of academic norms. It is a "learner centered" (a.k.a. "student centered" or "child centered") approach

PAGE 17

17 of 32to teaching (DarlingHammond, Griffin and Wise, 19 92) meaning that the teaching process is constrained by developmental considerations but the product is open ended. It is an approach that rejects both expectations for accomplishment based on curricular benchmarks or peer referenced norms as well as any "artificial" means of insuring that they materialize. In contrast, "educationally appropriate" instructio n (Stone, 1994) seeks to meet recognized standards and to otherwise maximize academic achiev ement. Both developmentally appropriate and educationally appropriate instruction rely on p resent levels of demonstrated performance as a starting point for instruction and both seek to opt imize intellectual advancement. Educationally appropriate teaching (or practice), however, does n ot treat present performance as a marker for a child's developmental limits. It is "learning cente red" in the sense that observed performance, not presumed developmental limitations, guides academic advancement. Although sensitive to student comfort with teaching practice, educational ly appropriate practice holds achievement, not developmental suitability, to be its top priority a nd neither does it presume high expectations or teacher insistence on effort to be developmentally hazardous. In conclusion, developmentalism appears to discoura ge teacher and parent intervention while simultaneously promoting the belief that acad emic achievement and responsible behavior will spontaneously emerge if only given time and fa cilitating conditions. Contrary to developmentalist expectations, however, it may be t hat awaiting the emergence of wholesome behavior is an open invitation to default contingen cies and the growth of unfavorable habits--ones that might have been precluded by the acquisition of appropriate patterns. By the time the realities of such deficits and/or inapprop riate conduct make the need for action inarguable, remediation is likely to be more diffic ult. Well ingrained patterns of faulty behavior must first be eliminated before constructive altern atives can be established--a situation all too familiar to special educators and school psychologi sts. The Developmentalist Neglect of Experimentally Vind icated Teaching Practices Developmentalism influences teacher acceptance of e xperimentally demonstrated teaching practices in much the same way it impacts teaching and parenting generally. It argues against intervention on the grounds that it is likely to de tract from the more optimal outcome that presumably will emerge when natural developmental p rocesses are permitted to run their course. Some Neglected Methodologies Over the last thirty years, a variety of experiment ally vindicated teaching methods have been developed and disseminated only to be ignored or discarded in favor of less well tested practices that better fit developmental thinking. M astery learning and Personalized System of Instruction may be the best known examples (Kulik, Kulik, & Bangert-Drowns, 1990). Direct Instruction (Becker & Carnine, 1980)--also known as DISTAR (Kim, Berger, & Kratochvil, 1972) and as "systematic instruction" (Slavin, 1994 )--is another. Direct Instruction is little used despite having been as thoroughly validated and fie ld tested as any methodology in the history of education (Watkins, 1988). These and a large group of structured and sequenced teaching methodologies termed "explicit teaching" (Rosenshin e, 1986) are among the most clear instances of experimentally supported approaches to teaching that have failed to gain widespread acceptance and/or have been abandoned. Programmed instruction (Skinner, 1958) is another e xample of an abandoned methodology and one that uniquely appears to demonstrate how de velopmentalism's hold on the teaching profession influences teaching practices in public schools. Despite its initial acceptance and evident promise, K-12 educators rejected programmed instruction in favor of less structured, more naturalistic, "real-world," "hands-on" approac hes (Skinner, 1986). However, among

PAGE 18

18 of 32educators less influenced by developmentalism, i.e. private sector business and industrial trainers, military trainers, designers of computerbased instruction, etc., it remained well established (Ellson, 1986; Vargas & Vargas, 1992). Many of the experimentally validated methodologies are behavioral because behavioral approaches to teaching and learning are derived fro m the experimental analysis of behavior. However, mastery learning (Bloom, 1976) and the "ex plicit teaching" methodologies discussed by Rosenshine (1986) are not behavioral and the sam e can be said for most of the "productive" methodologies discussed by Ellson (1986) and Walber g (1990, 1992). Ellson (1986) listed seventy-five studies of teaching methods all of whi ch report learning effects that are at least twice as great as control comparisons. Most of these meth ods were popular at one time but none are in widespread use today. Walberg (1990, 1992) summariz ed the results of nearly 8000 studies that point to the efficacy of a brief list of powerful a nd teacheralterable classroom interventions, most of which are supported by experimental evidenc e. High expectations for effort and achievement is one, the use of incentives is anothe r. In general, the neglected methodologies identified by Walberg and Ellson are structured and teacher directed; they aim to instill preconceived academic and intellectual outcomes; an d most of them employ practice, feedback, and incentives.Developmentally Inspired Concerns, Reservations, an d Objections Teaching methods textbooks and other sources of rec ommendations about teaching practice seem to sanction the disuse of experimenta lly vindicated methodologies either by giving them little or no attention or by discussing them i n the context of various concerns, objections, and reservations (Jacobsen, Eggen, & Kauchak, 1993; Ornstein, 1992; Wlodkowski, 1986). These remarks are especially noticeable when contra sted to the uncritical treatment given developmentally compatible methodologies. Typical c autions and criticisms involve claims that the experimentally vindicated methods are insuffici ently individualized (Armstrong, 1980), too artificial and mechanical (Bailey, 1991), excessive ly reliant on extrinsic motivation (Kohn, 1993a, 1993b), suited only to lower forms of learni ng (Ornstein, 1992), or simply boring (Henson, 1993; Lemlech, 1994). Virtually all of the se reservations and objections are premised on a developmentalist view of learning. Developmentalists hold that adherence to that which is developmentally appropriate is more important than educational achievement thus th ey favor educational experiences that are well accepted by students over those that are known to produce results. In the developmentalist view, teachers should seek methods that produce res ults but they should select them only from among those methods that maximize student satisfact ion. Judged by priorities so ordered, experimentally vindicated teaching methodologies ar e suspect at best because they are built around the notion that learning is the primary cons ideration. If the authors of methods textbooks were to suggest that teachers should prefer methodo logies that have been experimentally vindicated, they would be in disagreement with deve lopmentalist doctrine, i.e., with the view that student satisfaction is primary and learning second ary. The same consideration applies to teacher expectations for student effort and achievement. De velopmentalism suggests that teachers should expect a commitment to schoolwork that is commensur ate with the student's lifestyle and developmentally determined inclinations, not with e xternal and artificial requirements that are based on arbitrary or socially derived academic sta ndards. In effect, developmentalism requires experimentally vindicated practices not only to be attractive, interesting, and engaging, it obliges t hem to overcome the belief that they are likely to be risky or harmful, i.e. that they interfere in un known or unsuspected ways with a virtually boundless range of developmental considerations (El kind, 1981). The test of usefulness to which demonstrably effective interventions are subjected is not one of observed cost and benefit

PAGE 19

19 of 32compared to the observed cost and benefit of an exi sting alternative, it is one that entails suspected hidden cost versus the perfection that hy pothetically emerges in the absence of human interference. For example, when "whole language" proponents expre ss concern about skill-sequence approaches to reading (Goodman & Goodman, 1979), th ey worry that the interest in reading that otherwise naturally emerges might be lessened. Crit icisms of drill, corrective feedback, and the use of incentives are typically founded on the same argument. If, however, nature is permitted the opportunity (i.e., a "developmentally appropriate" opportunity) to work its effects, developmentalists assume that the expected skills a nd interest will emerge and without exposure to the hazards inherent in intervention (Clark & St arr, 1991; Lemlech, 1994; Jacobsen, Eggen, & Kauchak, 1993; Stone, 1995).The Alleged Threat to Intrinsic Motivation. Some developmentally inspired reservations about ex perimentally vindicated methodologies are based on more than theoretical ex trapolations. For example, the concerns about reductions in intrinsic motivation due to pos itive reinforcement reported by Deci & Ryan (1985), Lepper, Greene, & Nisbett (1973), and Schwa rtz (1990) appear to be supported by credible empirical findings. Even these claims, how ever, seem to have been exaggerated without challenge perhaps as a result of developmentalism's enormous influence within the educational community. For the past seventy-five or so years, the teaching profession has idealized learning that is motivated by interest as the only "true" learning. Led by Dewey (1916/1963; 1938/1963), the mainstream teaching profession has held that such intrinsic" or naturally occurring interest will express itself provided that the student is confron ted with a sufficiently meaningful or relevant or lifelike problem. Thus teaching that relies on extr insic sources of motivation is, according to Dewey's concept, inherently poor teaching, i.e., in sufficiently creative, innovative, and stimulating, and its use of extrinsic incentives a concession to faulty educational practice. The widespread acceptance of Dewey's developmentally in formed vision seems likely to have contributed to the positive reception given the rep orts of Deci, Ryan, Lepper, et al. and, more recently, to Kohn's (1993a, 1993b) wholesale deroga tion of positive reinforcement, incentives, rewards, and competition. The technical foundations of these reports, however have been the subject of scholarly disagreement, and the exaggerated nature of their c laims has become evident in the recent meta-analysis by Cameron and Pierce (1994). Reviewi ng the literature from 1971 to the present, they conclude that the empirical findings with resp ect to intrinsic motivation simply do not warrant exclusion of incentives from the classroom. One other telling observation may be made about Koh n's (1993a, 1993b) criticisms. Positive reinforcement and other extrinsic sources of motivation have been successfully employed by school psychologists, special educators and teachers of remedial and "at risk" students for many years (Hallahan, Kauffman, & Lloy d, 1985; Hammill & Bartel, 1990). Apparently that evidence has been overlooked or dis counted. Perhaps such applications are considered exempt from developmentalist strictures because students to whom they are applied have acknowledged developmental imperfections. Despite their success, however, interventions that are known to benefit the disabled are not entirely immune from criticism. For example, there is ongoing debate among early childhood special educators regarding "early intervention" ve rsus "developmentally appropriate practice." Again, the question is one of whether successful ex perimentally founded intervention strategies are producing some subtle but as-yetunnoticed dev elopmental harm (Carta, Schwartz, Atwater & McConnell, 1991; Johnson & Johnson, 1992).

PAGE 20

20 of 32The Alleged Inattention to Thinking. Of the developmentally inspired concerns pertaining to experimentally vindicated teaching methods, their alleged neglect of student thinking is, by far, the most frequent criticism (Armstrong & Savage, 1994; Callahan, Clark, & Kello ugh, 1992; Clark & Starr, 1991; Henson, 1993; Jacobsen, Eggen, & Kauchak, 1993; Kim & Kello ugh, 1995; Lemlech, 1994; Ornstein, 1992; Sheperd & Ragan, 1992). These concerns and th e current pedagogical emphasis on cognitive processes, higher-order intellectual skil ls, critical thinking, reflective thinking, etc., again, reflect Dewey's (1916/1963) view of learning : The sole direct path to enduring improvement in the methods of instruction and learning consists in centering upon the conditions which exact, promote, and test thinking. Thinking is the method of intelligen t learning, of learning that employs and rewards the mind. (p. 153) The same can be said of the present day emphasis on hands-on, authentic, real-world learning experiences as a means of facilitating learning: Only by wrestling with the conditions of . [a] problem at first hand, seeking and finding his own way out, does . [the student] think. When the paren t or teacher has provided the conditions which stimul ate thinking and has taken a sympathetic attitude towar d the activities of the learner by entering into a common or conjoint experience, all has been done which a seco nd party can do to instigate learning. The rest lies w ith the one directly concerned. (Dewey, 1916/1963, p. 1 60) Both Dewey (1916/1963) and Piaget (Siegler, 1991) c onsidered human learning capabilities the product of evolutionary demands fo r intellectual adaptation to the natural world. Formal knowledge and skills were held to be importa nt only to the extent that they were integrated with applications to problem solving. If natural circumstances required humans to learn and employ knowledge in the context of proble m solving, Dewey reasoned that schools would optimize learning by doing the same. Thus in Dewey's scheme of education, thinking in service of problem solving is primary to education and acquisition of formal knowledge and competencies is secondary and incidental. What Dewey may not have adequately considered is th at traits evolved under one set of conditions can prove useful under other conditions and in service of entirely different ends. For example, human hands were not initially selectedf or because of their usefulness in writing or musical performance but they subsequently served th at purpose. Analogously, the ability to acquire and retain knowledge may have been selected -for under conditions where knowledge was wholly contextualized, yet today the same ability c an be usefully employed to acquire knowledge that is partly or wholly decontextualized. Given the advantages that industrial and technologi cal cultures appear to derive from formal instruction afforded in a classroom setting, it seems evident that a profitable use has been found for the human ability to acquire factual, abs tract, and decontextualized knowledge and that acquisition of such knowledge is a useful prerequis ite to real-world, problem solving experiences. In fact, it would seem that schooling in societies which make use of the formal knowledge cumulated from the experiences of innumer able ancestors would necessarily entail a

PAGE 21

21 of 32substantial amount of decontextualized learning. Th us the achievement of preconceived objectives through experimentally vindicated teachi ng methodologies may afford socially, economically, and pedagogically advantageous gains in educational efficiency despite its inconsistency with the ideals inherent in Dewey, Pi aget, and other popular theorists. Why Non-experimental Research is Better Accepted In contrast to the skepticism typically encountered by experimentally founded interventions, teaching practices informed by studi es of naturally occurring social and educational processes are relatively well received by the educational community. Even if not adapted to developmental considerations, such pract ices do not suggest artificially imposed alterations of "natural" conditions. Thus if peer i nteraction processes or certain teacher or student characteristics are found to be correlated with stu dent achievement, teachers can be safely encouraged to take advantage of these "natural" (an d presumably causal) relationships by creatively interpreting and selectively employing t hem as developmental considerations permit. Studies of relationships between educational outcom es and student learning styles (Dunn, Beaudrey, & Klavas, 1989; Shipman & Shipman, 1985) are a good example. The recent surge of recommendations favoring greater sensitivity to mul ticultural diversity in the schools also seem founded on this type of research (Boykin, 1986; Tho mpson, Entwisle, Alexander, & Sundius, 1992). In each case, these studies encourage teache rs to shape instruction to the preferences and inclinations of the student in order to enhance ach ievement to the extent that student proclivities will permit. Unfortunately, of course, the causal inferences sug gested by descriptive and correlational studies can be grossly misleading and their misinte rpretation has lead to some of the most egregious instances of faulty teaching practice. Th e attempt to improve learning by boosting selfesteem is a prime example (Scheirer & Kraut, 1979).The Incompatibility of Developmental and Experiment al Views Given the nature of the developmentalist view, expe rimentally demonstrated teaching practices are bound to invite a great degree of ske pticism. The object of experimental research is to demonstrate the impact of an independent variabl e as an agent of change. Contrary to such an objective, developmentalism requires that social, e motional, and cognitive change emerge, not as an effect induced by an external agent, but as an i ndependent expression of the student. Thus experimentally tested methodologies are automatical ly considered suspect if not outrightly objectionable depending on which developmental limi tations are presumed applicable. In effect, developmentalist doctrine discourages reliance on t he most important and most credible research educators have at their disposal (Bloom, 1980 as ci ted in Gage & Berliner, 1992; Cook & Campbell, 1979). Because they claim an applicability that never seem s adequately tempered by developmental considerations, experimentally valida ted methods tend to encounter an impassable gauntlet of questions and reservations. In a refere nce to Walberg's (1984) report of generalizable, robust, and teacheralterable influences on learni ng, Ralph Tyler (1984) expressed the forlorn hope that the (developmentalist) notion that each s tudent and each circumstance is so unique that it can only be understood (i.e., effectively taught ) by a teacher deeply immersed in the situation would be dispelled. Armstrong (1980) raised the same issue in discussin g teacher demand for educational research: Given the nature of undergraduate teacher preparati on programs and the cultural

PAGE 22

22 of 32milieux of large numbers of schools, many teachers have come to believe that teaching is more art than science. Exposed to much talk about "individual differences" and "unique characteristics" of every classroom, many view teaching and teaching problems as situation-specific. Throug h their training and interactions with many colleagues, large numbers of teachers are more predisposed to acknowledge the differences than the commonalties c haracterizing the human condition. Consequently, many teachers suspect any generalized statements about human behavior. This orientation prompts many to do ubt the value of educational research efforts that, by design, seek generalizabl e knowledge. (p. 59) The restrictions on effective practice posed by dev elopmentalism have largely precluded many otherwise credible attempts to improve educati on through applications of science. The contrast between the degree of scientifically found ed progress in medicine versus that found in education attests this conclusion. To a large exten t, medical science has benefitted man by employing scientifically informed means of interven ing in nature. The artificial creation of immunities through the use of "unnatural" and invas ive vaccination is an historic example. In contrast, educational improvements on "natural" pat terns and processes of learning have been severely restricted by a doctrine of developmentali sm. Instead of using experimentally validated teaching methods, teachers have been encouraged to emulate nature and thereby preserve the perfection assumed to exist in natural developmenta l processes.Conclusion Developmentalism presumes typical patterns and proc esses of social, emotional, and cognitive change to be optimal because they are "na tural." It fails to recognize the extent to which valued social, emotional, and cognitive attri butes may be induced and sustained (not merely facilitated) by the purposeful actions of te achers and parents. Indeed, it seems to underestimate the importance of civilizing influenc es generally. By default, developmentalism ascribes the positive effects of unrecognized envir onmental influences to "natural" processes and argues that attempts to alter their effects are lik ely to be harmful. Present day developmentalism frames the process of socialization and, specifically, that of teaching as one of influencing the child in such a way as to avoid disruption of a postulated optimal outcome. It transforms teaching from an end eavor straightforwardly concerned with achievement to a search for naturalistic conditions that will fit the learner's tendencies in a way that permits the unfettered and, therefore presumab ly optimal, emergence of intellectual growth. Developmentalism assumes that teaching which deviat es from this general prescription is, at best, naive and, at worst, dangerous and destructiv e of the learner's best interests. Thus teaching practices uninformed by developmental consideration s are persistently rejected by the teaching profession regardless of demonstrated educational e ffectiveness and otherwise wholesome impact--a pervasive and powerful but largely unreco gnized restriction on scientifically founded educational improvement. ReferencesAlexander, R., Rose, J., & Woodhead, C. (1992). Cur ricular organization and classroom practice in primary schools, a discussion paper. London (SW1 P 3BT), United Kingdom: Department of Education and Science.Altwerger, B., Edelsky, C., & Flores, B. M. (1987). Whole language: What's new? The Reading Teacher, 41, 144-154.

PAGE 23

23 of 32American Legislative Exchange Council [ALEC], (1994 ). Report card on American education 1994. Washington, DC: Author.Armstrong, D. G. (1980). Researchers' incentives an d the dearth of practical research results. Peabody Journal of Education, 58, 55-60.Armstrong, D. G., & Savage, T. V. (1994). Secondary education, an introduction (4th ed.). New York: Macmillan.Axtelle, G. E., & Burnette, J. R. (1970). Dewey on education and schooling. In J. A. Boydston (Ed.), Guide to the works of John Dewey (pp. 257-30 5). Carbondale, IL: Southern Illinois University Press.Bailey, J. S. (1991). Marketing behavior analysis r equires different talk. Journal of Applied Behavior Analysis, 24, 445-448.Becker, W. & Carnine, D. (1980). Direct instruction : An effective approach for educational intervention with the disadvantaged and low perform ers. In B. Lahey and A.Kazdin (Eds.), Advances in child clinical psychology. New York: Pl enum. Berliner, D. C., & Biddle, B. J. (1995). The manufa ctured crisis. New York: Addison-Wesley. Berliner, D. & Biddle, B. (1996, February). Making molehills out of molehills: Reply to Lawrence Stedman's review of The Manufactured Crisi s. Education Policy Analysis Archives, 4(3). http://olam.ed.asu.edu/epaa/Bigge, M. L., & Hunt, M. P. (1962). Psychological f oundations of education: An introduction to human development and learning. New York: Harper & Row. Binder, C., & Watkins, C. L. (1989). Promoting effe ctive instructional methods: Solutions to America's educational crisis. Future Choices, 1 (3) 33-39. Birnbaum, J. (1991, August 12). Crybabies: Eternal victims. Time, pp. 16-18. Bloom, B. S. (1976). Human characteristics and scho ol learning. New York: McGraw-Hill. Boydston, J. A. (Ed.). (1970). Guide to the works o f John Dewey. Carbondale, IL: Southern Illinois University Press.Boykin, A. W. (1986). The triple quandary and the s chooling of Afro-American children. In U. Neisser (Ed.), The school achievement of minority c hildren. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. Bracy, G. (1996). International comparisons and the condition of American education. Educational Researcher, 25(1), 5-11.Brazelton, T. B. (1974). Toddlers and parents. New York: Delacorte Press. Bredekamp, S. (1988). NAEYC position statement on d evelopmentally appropriate practice in the primary grades, serving 5 through 8 year olds. Young Children, January, pp. 64-84. Brooks, J. G., & Brooks, M. G. (1993). In search of understanding: The case for constructivist classrooms.

PAGE 24

24 of 32Alexandria, VA: Association for Supervision and Cur riculum Development. Brown, J. S., Collins, A., & Duguid, P. (1989). Sit uated cognition and the culture of learning. Educational Researcher, 18, 32-42.Bruner, J. S. (1966). Toward a theory of instructio n. New York: Norton. Callahan, J. F., Clark, L. H., & Kellough, R. D. (1 992).Teaching in the middle and secondary schools (4th ed.).New York: Macmillan.Cameron, J., & Pierce, W. D. (1994). Reinforcement, reward, and intrinsic motivation: a meta-analysis. Review of Educational Research, 64(3 ), 363-423. Campbell, D. & Stanley, J. (1963). Experimental and quasi-experimental designs for research. Skokie, IL: Rand McNally.Carnine, D. (1993, December 8). Facts over fads.Edu cation Week, p. 40. Carnine, D. (1995, May 3). Is innovation always goo d? Education Week, p. 40. Carta, J. J., Schwartz, I. S., Atwater, J. B., & Mc Connell, S. R. (1991). Developmentally appropriate practice: Appraising its usefulness for young children with disabilities. Topics in Early Childhood Special Education, 11 (1), 1-20.Case, R. (Ed.). (1991). The mind's staircase: Stage s in the development of human intelligence. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.Clark, L. H., & Starr, I. S. (1991). Secondary and middle school teaching methods (6th ed.). New York: Macmillan.Committee for Economic Development. (1991). The unf inished agenda: A new vision for child development and education (A statement by the Resea rch and Policy Committee for the Committee for Economic Development). New York: Auth or. Cook, T. D., & Campbell, D. T. (1979). Quasiexper imentation, design & analysis issues for field settings. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.Cremin, L. A. (1964). The transformation of the sch ool, progressivism in American education 1876-1957. New York: Vintage Books.Darling-Hammond, L., Griffin, G., Wise, A. (1992).E xcellence in teacher education: Helping teachers develop learner-centered schools. Washingt on, DC: National Education Association. Deci, E. L., & Ryan, R. M. (1985). Intrinsic motiva tion and self-determination in human behavior. New York: Plenum.Dewey, J. (1916/1963). Democracy and education. New York: The Macmillan Company. Dewey, J. (1938/1963). Experience and education. Ne w York: Collier Books. Dunn, R., Beaudrey, J. S., & Klavas, A. (1989). Sur vey of research on learning styles. Educational Leadership, 46(6), pp. 50-58.

PAGE 25

25 of 32Elkind, D. (1981). The hurried child. Newton, MA: A ddisonWesley. Ellson, D. (1986, October). Improving productivity in teaching. Phi Delta Kappan, pp. 111-124. El-Nemr, M. A. (1980). A meta-analysis of the outco mes of teaching biology as inquiry (Doctoral dissertation, University of Colorado, 197 9). Dissertation Abstracts International, 40, 5813A. (University Microfilms International No. 8011274) Feldman, W. T. (1934/1968). The philosophy of John Dewey, a critical analysis. New York: Greenwood Press.Freedman, J. (1993). Failing grades, Canadian schoo ling in a global economy. Red Deer, Alberta, Canada: Society for Advancing Educational Research.Furth, H. G. & Wachs, H. (1975). Thinking goes to s chool, Piaget's theory in practice. New York: Oxford University Press.Gage, N. L. & Berliner, D. C. (1992). Educational p sychology. Boston: Houghton Mifflin. Gesell, A. & Ilg, F. L. (1940). The first five year s of life; a guide to the study of the preschool child. New York: Harper.Gesell, A. & Ilg, F. L. (1943). Infant and child in the culture of today. New York: Harper and Row.Gesell, A. & Ilg, F. L. (1946). The child from five to ten.New York: Harper. Gesell, A., Ilg, F. L., & Ames, L. B. (1956). Youth : The years from ten to sixteen. New York: Harper.Giacomia, R. M., & Hedges, L. V. (1982). Identifyin g features of effective open education. Review of Educational Research, 52, 579-602.Goodman, Y., & Goodman, K. S. (1979). Learning to r ead is natural. In L. B. Resnick & P. A. Weaver (Eds.), Theory and practice of early reading (Vol. 1, pp. 137154).Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.Green, F. C. (1955). Jean Jacques Rousseau: A criti cal study of his life and writings. New York: Cambridge University Press.Guskey, T. R., & Pigott, T. D. (1988). Research on groupbased mastery learning programs: A metaanalysis.Journal of Educational Research. 81, 197-216. Hall, G. S. (1907). Youth, its education, regimen, and hygiene. New York: Appleton. Hallahan, D. P., Kauffman, J. M., & Lloyd, J. W. (1 985).Introduction to learning disabilities (2nd ed.).Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.Hammill, D. D. & Bartel, N. R. (1990). Teaching stu dents with learning and behavior problems (5th ed.). Boston: Allyn and Bacon.Heinemann. (1995). Books for teachers K-8, 1995.(Ca talogue available from Heinemann-Boyton/Cook, College Department, 361 Hano ver St., Portsmouth, NH 03801)

PAGE 26

26 of 32Henson, K. T. (1993). Methods and strategies for te aching in secondary schools (2nd ed.). New York: Longman.Hetzel, D. C., Rasher, S. P, Butcher, L., & Walberg H. J.(1980). A quantative synthesis of the effects of open education. American Educational Res earch Association. (ERIC Document Reproduction Service No. ED 191 902) Holton, G. (1993). Science and anti-science. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Pre ss. Jacobsen, D., Eggen, P., & Kauchak, D. (1993). Meth ods for teaching, a skills approach (4th ed.). New York: Merrill.James, W. (1899/1924). Talks to teachers on psychol ogy: and to students on some of life's ideals. New York: Henry Holt and Company.Johnson, J. E., & Johnson, K. M. (1992). Clarifying the developmental perspective in response to Carta, Schwartz, Atwater, and McConnell. Topics in Early Childhood Special Education, 12(4), 439-457.Kantrowitz, B., & Wingert, P. (1993, November). Fai ling the most gifted students. Newsweek, p. 67.Kentucky Education Reform Act of 1990, KRS }} 156.0 10 (1990) Kim, E. C. & Kellough, R. D. (1995). A resource gui de for secondary school teaching, planning for competence (6th ed.). New Jersey: Prentice Hall Kim, Y., Berger, B. J., & Kratochvil, D. W. (1972). Distar Instructional System (Product Development Report No. 14).Palo Alto, CA: American Institute for Research. Kirsch, I. S., Jungblut, A., Jenkins, L., & Kolstad A. (1993, September). Adult Literacy in America (execu tive summary). Washington DC: U. S. Department of Education.Kohlberg, L., & Mayer, R. (1972). Development as th e aim of education. Harvard Educational Review, 42, 449496.Kohn, A. (1993a). Punished by rewards: the trouble with gold stars, incentive plans, A's, praise, and other bribes. New York: Houghton Mifflin.Kohn, A. (1993b). Rewards versus learning: A respon se to Paul Chance. Phi Delta Kappan, pp. 783-787.Kulik, C. -L., Kulik, J. A., & Bangert-Drowns, R. L (1990).Effectiveness of mastery learning programs: A metaanalysis. Review of Educational R esearch, 60(2), pp. 265299. Kurtz, P. (1994, March 12). The growth of antisci ence.The Skeptical Inquirer, 18(3), p. 255. Lemlech, J. (1994). Curriculum and instructional me thods for the elementary and middle school (3rd ed.). New York: Macmillan College.Lepper, M. R., Greene, D., & Nisbett, R. E. (1973). Undermining children's intrinsic interest with

PAGE 27

27 of 32extrinsic reward: A test of the "overjustification" hypothesis.Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 28, 129-137.Lysakowski, R. S., & Walberg, H. J. (1980). Classro om reinforcement. Evaluation in Education, 4, 115-116.Lysakowski, R. S., & Walberg, H. J. (1981). Classro om reinforcement and learning: A quantative synthesis. Journal of Educational Research, 75, 6977. Lysakowski, R. S., & Walberg, H. J. (1982). Instruc tional effects of cues, participation, and feedback: A quantative synthesis. American Educatio nal Research Journal, 19(2), 559-578. Madamba, S. R. (1981). Meta-analysis on the effects of open and traditional schooling on the teaching-learning of reading (Doctoral dissertation University of California, Los Angeles, 1980). Dissertation Abstracts International, 41, 3508A. (U niversity Microfilms International No. 8102856)McCullers, J. C. (1969). G. Stanley Hall's concepti on of mental development and some indicators of its influence on developmental psychology. Ameri can Psychologist, 24, 1109-1114. Makari, G. J. (1993). Educated insane: A nineteenth century psychiatric paradigm. Journal of the History of the Behavioral Sciences, 29, 8-21.Mandel, M. J., Melcher, R. A., Yang, D. J., & McNam ee, M. (1995, April 17). Will schools ever get better? Business Week, pp. 18-21.Marshall, J. (1993, December). Why Johnny can't tea ch. Reason, pp. 31-35. May, H. (1959). The end of American innocence. New York: Alfred A. Knopf, Inc. McGraw, M. B. (1945/1969). The neuromuscular matura tion of the human infant. New York: Hafner Publishing Company.National Education Association. (1995). If teacher training is your interest. (NEA Professional Library Publications catalogue available from the N ational Education Association, 1201 16th. St. N.W., Washington, DC 200363290)Ornstein, A. C. (1992). Secondary and middle school teaching methods. New York: Harper Collins.Organization for Economic Co-operation and Developm ent [OECD], (1994). OECD economic surveys 1993-1994: United States.Paris, France: Author (OECD Publications, 2 rue And rePascal, 75775 Paris CEDEX 16). Overton, W. F. (1972). Piaget's theory of intellect ual development and progressive education. In J. R. Squire (Ed.). A new look at progressive educa tion (pp. 88-115). Washington, DC: Association for Supervision and Curriculum Developm ent. Peterson, P. L. (1980). Open versus traditional cla ssrooms.Evaluation in Education, 4, 58-60. Ravitch, D. (1983). The troubled crusade: American education 1945-1980. New York: Harper-Collins.

PAGE 28

28 of 32Reschly, D., & Sabers, D. (1974). Open education: H ave we been here before? Phi Delta Kappan, 55, (10), 675-677.Riegel, K. (1972). Influence of economic and politi cal ideologies on the development of developmental psychology. Psychological Bulletin, 7 8(2), 129-141. Riley, R. W. (1993, April). Statement by Richard W. Riley, U. S. secretary of education on the national assessment of educational progress 1992 ma thematics report card for the nation and the states. Washington, DC: U. S. Department of Educati on. Rosenshine, B. V. (1986). Synthesis of research on explicit teaching. Educational Leadership, 43(7), 60-69.Rusk, R. R. (1965). The doctrines of the great educ ators. Revised and enlarged third edition, New York: St. Martins Press.Scheirer, M. A., & Kraut, R. E. (1979). Increasing educational achievement via self concept change. Review of Educational Research, 49(1), 131150. Schwartz, B. (1990). The creation and destruction o f value. American Psychologist, 45, 7-15. Sheperd, G. D., & Ragan, W. B. (1992). Modern eleme ntary curriculum (7th ed.). Fort Worth: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich College.Shipman, S., & Shipman, V. (1985). Cognitive styles : Some conceptual, methodological and applied issues. In E. W.Gordon (Ed.), Review of Edu cational Research, Vol. 12. Washington, DC: American Educational Research Association.Shine, B. (1993). Let's be realistic about what tea chers can accomplish. (Available from Committee to Elect Shine for Governor, 433 East Cen ter Street, Kingsport, TN 37660) Siegler, R. S. (1991). Children's thinking (2nd ed. ). Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall. Skinner, B. F. (1958). Teaching machines. Science, 128, 969-977. Skinner, B. F. (1986, October). Programmed instruct ion revisited. Phi Delta Kappan, pp. 103-110.Slavin, R. E. (1994). Educational psychology, theor y and practice. Boston: Allyn and Bacon. Slavin, R. E. (1991). Educational Psychology. Engle wood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall. Spock, B. (1976). Baby and child care (Rev. Ed.). N ew York: Pocket Books. Sprinthall, N. A., & Sprinthall, R. C. (1987). Educ ational psychology: A developmental approach (4th ed.). New York: Random House.Squire, J. R. (Ed.). (1972). A new look at progress ive education. Washington, DC: Association for Supervision and Curriculum Development.Stahl, S. A., & Miller, P. D. (1989). Whole languag e and language experience approaches for beginning reading: A quantitative research synthesi s. Review of Educational Research, 59, 87-116.

PAGE 29

29 of 32Stanovich, K. E. (1992). How to think straight abou t psychology (3rd. ed.). New York: Harper Collins.Stanovich, K. E. (1993). Romance and reality. The R eading Teacher, 47(4), pp. 280-291. Stedman, L. C. (1996, January). The achievement cri sis is real. [Review of The Manufactured Crisis]. Education Policy Analysis Archives, 4(1). http://olam.ed.asu.edu/epaa/ Stedman, L. C. (1996, April). Respecting the eviden ce: The achievement crisis remains real. Education Policy Analysis Archives, 4(7). http:// o lam.ed.asu.edu/epaa/ Stone, J. E. (1991). Developmentalism: A standing i mpediment to the design of the "New American School." Network News & Views, 10 (12), 13. Stone, J. E. (1993a, August). Behavioral technology in a developmentalist context. In S. Axelrod (Chair), Educational technology concepts and appl ications. An invited symposium held at the 101st Annual Convention of the American Psychologic al Association, Toronto, Ontario, Canada. Stone, J. E. (1993b). An open letter to the Oregon state governing bodies. Effective School Practices, 12(2), 3-6.Stone, J. E. (1994). Developmentalism's impediments to school reform: Three recommendations for overcoming them. In Ralph Gardner III, Diane M. Sainato, John O. Cooper, Timothy E. Heron, William L. Heward, John W. Eshleman, & Teres a A. Grossi (Eds.), Behavior analysis in education: Focus on measurably superior instruction Pacific Grove, CA: Brooks/Cole. Stone, J. E., (1995, May). Motivational recommendat ions found in popular teaching methods textbooks. In C. McMahon (Chair), Conceptual and Th eoretical Issues in Education and Educational Reform. A paper presented at the 21st A nnual Convention of the Association for Behavior Analysis, Washington, DC.Strickland, C. E. & Burgess, C. (Eds.). (1965). Hea lth, growth, and heredity, G. Stanley Hall on natural education. New York: Teachers College Press Survey: Fewer skilled workers. (1991, December 10). Johnson City Press, p. 14. Teal, W. & Sulzby, E. (1987). Emergent literacy: Wr iting and reading. Norwood, N. J.: Ablex, 1987.Tomlinson, T. (1992). Hard work and high expectatio ns: Motivating students to learn (Superintendent of Documents, P. O. Box 371954, Pit tsburgh, PA 15250-7954; order #06500496-8). Washington, DC: Office of Research and Im provement, U. S. Department of Education.Thompson, M. S., Entwisle, D. R., Alexander, K. L., & Sundius, M. J. (1992). The influence of family composition on children's conformity to the student role.American Educational Research Journal, 29(2), 405-424.Tyler, R. (1984). A guide to educational troubles hooting.Educational Leadership, 41, 27-30. U.S. Department of Education. (1991). America 2000, an education strategy (revised). Washington, DC: Author.

PAGE 30

30 of 32 Vargas, E. A. & Vargas, J. S. (1992). Programmed in struction and teaching machines. In R. P. West & L. A. Hamerlynck (Eds.), Designs for excelle nce in education: The legacy of B. F. Skinner (limited edition, pp. 33-69). Longmont, CO: Sopris West, Inc. Vygotsky, L. S. (1987). The collected works of L. S Vygotsky (translated by Rieber and Carton). New York: Plenum.Walberg, H. J. (1990, February). Productive teachin g and instruction: Assessing the knowledge base. Phi Delta Kappan, pp. 470-478.Walberg, H. J. (1992). The knowledge base for teach er productivity. International Journal of Educational Reform, 1 (1), 1-10.Walberg, H. J. (1984). Improving the productivity o f America's schools. Educational Leadership, 41, 19-27.Wang, M. C., Reynolds, M. C., & Walberg, H. J. (198 7). Handbook of special education. New York: Pergamon.Warner, S. L. & Rosenberg, E. B. (1976). Your child learns naturally. New York: Doubleday. Watkins, C. L. (1988, July). Project follow through : A story of the identification and neglect of effective instruction. Youth Policy, pp. 7-11.Weber, E. (1972). Conceptions of child growth and l earning. In J. R. Squire (Ed.). A new look at progressive education (pp. 16-43). Washington, DC: Association for Supervision and Curriculum Development.Westbury, I. (1992). Comparing American and Japanes e achievement: Is the United States really a low achiever? Educational Researcher, 21(5), 18-2 4. Wlodkowski, R. J. (1986). Motivation and teaching: A practical guide. Washington DC: National Education Association.About the Author J. E. Stone is a professor in the Department of Hum an Development and Learning at East Tennessee State University. An Ed. D. graduate of t he University of Florida, he is a licensed educational psychologist and school psychologist. S ince 1972, he has taught more than 10,000 classes in ETSU's College of Education. His primary scholarly interest is educational reform in both K-12 and higher education. Currently, he heads the Education Consumers Clearinghouse--an internet networking and informati on resource for parents and other consumers of education.P. O. Box 70548, ETSUJohnson City, TN 37614(423) 439-4190stonej@access.etsu-tn.eduCopyright 1996 by the Education Policy Analysis Archives

PAGE 31

31 of 32EPAA can be accessed either by visiting one of its seve ral archived forms or by subscribing to the LISTSERV known as EPAA at LISTSERV@asu.edu. (To sub scribe, send an email letterto LISTSERV@asu.edu whose sole contents are SUB EPAA y our-name.) As articles are published by the Archives they are sent immediately to the EPAA subscribers and simultaneously archived in three forms. Articles are archived on EPAA as individual files under the name of the author a nd the Volume and article number. For example, the article by Stephen Kemmis in Volume 1, Number 1 of the Archives can be retrieved by sending an e-mail letter to LISTSERV@a su.edu and making the single line in the letter rea d GET KEMMIS V1N1 F=MAIL. For a table of contents of the entire ARCHIVES, send the following e-mail message to LISTSERV@asu.edu: INDEX EPAA F=MAIL, tha t is, send an e-mail letter and make its single line read INDEX EPAA F=MAIL.The World Wide Web address for the Education Policy Analysis Archives is http://olam.ed.asu.edu/ Education Policy Analysis Archives are "gophered" in the directory Campus-Wide Inform ation at the gopher server INFO.ASU.EDU.To receive a publication guide for submitting artic les, see the EPAA World Wide Web site or sendan e-mail letter to LISTSERV@asu.edu and include the single l ine GET EPAA PUBGUIDE F=MAIL. It will be sent to you by return e-mail. General questions about ap propriateness of topics or particular articles may be addressed to the Editor, Gene V Glass,Glass@asu.edu or reach him at College of Education,Arizona State University, Tempe, AZ 85287-2411. (602-965-2692)Editorial Board John Covaleskiejcovales@nmu.edu Andrew Coulson andrewco@ix.netcom.com Alan Davis adavis@castle.cudenver.edu Mark E. Fetlermfetler@ctc.ca.gov Thomas F. Greentfgreen@mailbox.syr.edu Alison I. Griffithagriffith@edu.yorku.ca Arlen Gullickson gullickson@gw.wmich.edu Ernest R. Houseernie.house@colorado.edu Aimee Howleyess016@marshall.wvnet.edu Craig B. Howley u56e3@wvnvm.bitnet William Hunterhunter@acs.ucalgary.ca Richard M. Jaeger rmjaeger@iris.uncg.edu Benjamin Levinlevin@ccu.umanitoba.ca Thomas Mauhs-Pughthomas.mauhspugh@dartmouth.edu Dewayne Matthewsdm@wiche.edu Mary P. McKeowniadmpm@asuvm.inre.asu.edu Les McLeanlmclean@oise.on.ca Susan Bobbitt Nolensunolen@u.washington.edu Anne L. Pembertonapembert@pen.k12.va.us Hugh G. Petrieprohugh@ubvms.cc.buffalo.edu Richard C. Richardsonrichard.richardson@asu.edu Anthony G. Rud Jr.rud@sage.cc.purdue.edu

PAGE 32

32 of 32Dennis Sayersdmsayers@ucdavis.edu Jay Scribnerjayscrib@tenet.edu Robert Stonehillrstonehi@inet.ed.gov Robert T. Stoutstout@asu.edu

PAGE 33

1 of 10 Contributed Commentary on Volume 4 Number 8: Stone Developmentalism: An Obscu re but Pervasive Restriction on Educational Improvement June 10 1996 Don Tinkler dtinkler@schnet.edu.au I have some sympathy with the position taken by Pr of. Stone, and given the opportunity and the time, would like to discuss further with hi m the many claims he makes about moves in education over the past twenty or so years, whether in the United States or Australia. Having said that, I must protest that in applying 'developmentalism' as an umbrella term, Stone has ignored the distinctions between the vari ous sub-sets of developmentalism. In the abstract accompanying the paper, Stone concludes: ... its [developmentalism] most recent expressions include "developmentally appropriate practice" and "constructivism". In the years during which it gained ascendance, developmentalism served as a basis for rejecting harsh and inhumane teaching methods. Today it impedes efforts to hold schools accountable for student academic achievement. The inference seems to be that constructivism, bei ng a more recent expression, is the impediment. Prof. Stones' claim that 'constructivism discourag es teachers and parents from asserting themselves with children' indicates a failure to un derstand the importance for education of the shift not only to a practice that takes account of something more than behavioural outcomes, but to one where the provision of quality experiences e stablishes the mental connections that enable learners to construct more satisfactory understandi ngs of their individual realities. I concede that the early varieties of developmenta lism based on stages of development or stages of cognitive growth served as a basis for re jecting inappropriate (harsh and inhumane) teaching methods, and that many of the practices of the so-called childcentred movement failed because of complete lack of structure. However, I w ould need further convincing before agreeing that developmentalist (constructivist) practices co nstitute an impediment to strategies that might be applied to hold schools accountable for student academic achievement. There is of course the problem that professor Stone and I would probably b e in considerable disagreement on the definition of both the terms, "academic" and "achie vement." Perhaps the opening of the abstract could have mor e accurately have read: 'Because of continuing and justified criticism of public educat ion, much of the so-called "experimentally demonstrated" teaching methodology ought to have be en rejected and abandoned long ago.' "Constructivism" has developed from a rediscovery of the importance of "mind" in the teaching-learning equation. The resultant shift of emphasis has been from teaching to learning with teachers now having to ask themselves what mus t I do so that my students can learn with understanding, rather than asking what I must do to teach (instruc t)? Lauren Resnick (1983) asserted that:

PAGE 34

2 of 10... the accumulated body of cognitive task analysis and the emerging work on cognitive theories of acquisition clearly signal th e need for a constructivist theory of instruction. It now seems absolutely certain that our task is t o develop a theory that places the learner's active mental construction at the very heart of the instructional exchange. Instruction cannot simply put knowledge i nto people's heads. Instead, effective instruction must aim to place learners in situations where the constructions that they naturally and inevitably make as they try to make sense of their worlds are correct as well as sensible ones. (Resnick's emphases) My own contribution since the late seventies is ac cepted as essentially constructivist. As one of the pioneers, I applied the emerging theory to the development of curriculum in social education, providing an expanded form of social stu dies incorporating aspects of anthropology, economics, politics, the life sciences, earth scien ce, some mathematics as well as the more traditional history and geography at levels suitabl e for children in years K through 6. The curriculum was developed on what has become known a s the 'logical sequential' model, taking into account the need for higher order language ski lls and the factors of mental growth, development of concepts, the need for quality exper iences, values education, scope and sequence and spiral development of experiences and concepts. The theorising supporting its development and the original curriculum matrix chart, published in 1981, have generated numbers of articl es, papers and presentations which since 1984 have been delivered in all States of Australia and on visits to London, various cities in the US and Toronto. A teacher handbook with a revised v ersion of the chart, published in 1989 (2nd edition 1990) is widely dispersed and has received approval from educators in many other countries. A presention for the 10th World Congress on Gifted and Talented Education (1993), Toronto, Canada, encapsulates something of the theo ry and practice developed since 1981, and I include with this commentary the first few pages of that paper: A CURRICULUM THAT LIBERATES THE LEARNER Presentation for the 10th World Congress on Gifted and Talented Education, Toronto, Canada August 8 to 13, 1993 Don E Tinkler, Consultant in Education, Melbourne, Australia -----------------------------------------... the gulf between the mature or adult products a nd the experience and abilities of the young is so wide that the very situation forbid s much active participation by the pupils in the development of what is taught. Theirs is to do and learn... that which is taught is thought of as essentially static. It i s taught as a finished product, with little regard either to the ways in which it was or iginally built up or to changes that will surely occur in the future. It is to a large e xtent the cultural product of societies that assumed the future would be much like the past and yet it is used as educational food in a society where change is the r ule, not the exception. The problem for progressive education is: What is t he place and meaning of subject-matter and of organization within experienc e? It is not enough to insist upon the necessity of ex perience, or even the activity in experience. Everything depends upon the quality of the experience which is had.

PAGE 35

3 of 10John Dewey, 1938 (Dewey'semphases) ---------------------------------------------While attacking traditional schooling which imposed knowledge on students in a 'kind of institution sharply marked off from any ot her form of social organization', Dewey was also strong in his criticism of the 'prog ressives' for the way they had distorted his theory of experience to the extent th at any school experience was accepted as being as good as any other. Although ap proaching eighty years of age, to set the record straight, Dewey wrote Experience in Education from which these quotes are taken. It is a matter of history (Samples 1976) that Dewe y fell from favor when the United States was beaten in the space race by the R ussian Sputnik in 1957. Called to account for what was accepted as a national disgrac e, a conference of scientists and educators at Woods Hole in Massachusetts the follow ing year, chaired by Gerome Bruner, looked to the ideas of Jean Piaget to redir ect U.S. educational philosophy. So it was that Piaget's 'stages' theory was release d on the educational world in 1964. Piaget emerged as the dominant theorist, while Dewe y faded into relative obscurity. This paper will assert that it is time the learner was freed from the constraints imposed by traditional schooling as claimed by Dewe y, and yet offered more than 'progressive' education as an alternative. It will present an overview of more than fifteen y ears effort which has resulted in the generation of a 'constructivist' th eory of learning, a new curriculum design, the publication of The Humanities Core Curriculum (1981, 1989), a curriculum chart dealing with an expanded view of s ocial education, and a teacher handbook which explains how that curriculum can be individualized for regular classroom use or for pull-out programs for 'gifted' students. The innovative approach emphasizes learning with u nderstanding and provides new relevance to social education. At the same time it offers an opportunity to teachers to make more effective use of their dev eloped skills in curriculum planning, facilitating, monitoring, and evaluation. The handbook Social Education for Australian Primary Schools (2nd Ed. 1990) takes a fresh look at a wide range of educati onal and curriculum issues, unpacks some of the emerging theory about learning with understanding, and converts it into sound practice in social education Subtitled A 'Futures' Perspective, it was written for teachers and others engaged in h elping young people make sense of a very complex worldboth in the present and int o the longer term future. Skills Building For the Future Since no one can know the future, the plural form 'futures' is used. We can talk of 'possible', 'probable' and 'preferred' futu res. Possible futures take in anything that could possibly happen; probable futures refer to those that are likely to happen on the probability of certain things occurring or n ot occurring; and preferred futures refer to those that might be selected from the 'pro bable' futures as being more desirable. Professor David Suzuki of the University of Britis h Columbia in a broadcast in 1987 claimed that 'human beings have become the most reliable failure component in technology today'. Educators must ask why we should accept a future where human beings continue to be the most 'reliabl e failure components' in our

PAGE 36

4 of 10advancing technology? Attention of the world several years ago was focus ed upon literacy and the problems of illiteracy. However, we should perhaps then have been asking whether the level of literacy considered satisfactory in 19 50, or even as recently as 1980, will be suitable for the nineties and beyond. The theme for the Australian Reading Association F irst International Conference (1993) was Literacy For The New Millennium. Most speakers seemed to think that literacy for the new millennium meant li ttle more than holding to the status quoall students being expected to develop t he skills of reading, writing and listening. While conceding that there was much that we could do to develop more effective skills in these areas, there seemed littl e awareness of the recent reports of the OECD where reference was made to 'enterprise sk ills' as being like a 'third passport' enabling students to cross from school to the world outside. Nor did it seem that speakers knew of the parallel work of UNESCO a nd the call of its Symposium in Beijing late in 1989 for: a new view of knowledge; a greater integration of knowledge; a renewed commitment to lifelong learning; an education system with shifts of emphases from conformity to creativity and innovativeness, from competitiveness to co-operativeness, from private benefits of learning to public benef its, from instruction to learning how to learn, to nourishing the higher-order skills, to positive aspects of personal development, to promote tolerance in interrelating with others Taking account of the emerging ecological and glob al threats to survival, the UNESCO Symposium cautioned that educational planner s will need to restructure education to fit people for the twenty-first centur y, which, in their words, 'now will probably be rather different from what we would hav e predicted as recently as five years ago'. In the mid 1980s a 'Creative Cities' conference in Melbourne was told by its Keynote speaker, Dr. Rashmi Mayur, Director of the Urban Development Institute in Bombay and advisor to the United Nations and the U. S. Congress, that what was really needed was 'creative people', that is, peopl e who could think creatively about future needs and about future directions. It is cer tain that the most important resources in any future will be the human resources Tomorrow's people will need greater capacity for creating choices, and thinking through the choices between competing options. They will need also a wider rang e of personal skills--some of which we can only guess at today. All this points to the need perhaps to look at lit eracy in a different way as we approach the new millennium. Learner Monitored Learning In England the Royal Society for the encouragement of Arts, Manufactures and Commerce (RSA), has adopted 'Education for Capa bility', a program with major focus upon secondary schools and tertiary instituti ons. According to the RSA, 'Education for Capability is a practical nationwide campaign to develop the talents of

PAGE 37

5 of 10all young people and give them the confidence that comes with succes.' The RSA joined with the World Education Fellowship and several other institutions in convening the First International C onference on Learner Managed Learning in April 1990. At the conference, experiences were shared by thos e who had allowed learners to apply their 'enterprise' skills in prog rams of self directed learning and decision making. There were reports of learner cont racts, experiential learning, peer tutoring, inquiry and problem solving approaches ha ving been trialed. With time to reflect upon the issues of the confer ence, I am convinced that, at least in the formative years of primary and seconda ry school, and maybe even in tertiary education, the learner does not 'manage' b ut rather 'monitors' his/her learning processes. Just as in the one-teacher school, the m onitor works as a mediator under the guidance and supervision of the teacher, we cou ld look at self-directed learning as the learner mediating the learning processes wit h the teacher as manager or facilitator. Some years ago, Paul Brandwein (1977) suggested th at 'the child comes to school with a comprehension consisting of a world o f constructs, which we know to be somewhat faulty. But he comes, nevertheless, wit h an idiosyncratic way of learning'. It seems that the teacher's task is to discover th e idiosyncrasy, to help correct the faults in the constructs, and lead the child fo rward towards increased comprehension about the world. Teachers can help ch ildren become aware of their own learning--referred to as 'metacognition' or 'aw areness of awareness.' Monitoring one's learning will require the develop ment of a range of competencies for problem solving, research and data processing. Those competencies in turn will depend upon establishing the sub-skills of reflection, analysis, comparing, inference, classification, and synthesis--the so called 'thinking skills.' Thinking skills can be taught. Parents can encoura ge the development of a range of basic thinking strategies, but perhaps the most appropriate time to start training in thinking skills is when the child reach es the primary school. The Search for an Alternative Theory of Knowledge A cquisition The search for answers to questions arising from y ears of classroom teaching led me to look at various theories of knowledge 'ac quisition,' and then to examine what teachers might do to speed up and strengthen t he processes of acquisition. In the late 1960s I had been involved in the imple mentation of a new science approach derived from the Nuffield Science curricul um developed in the U.K., and had been impressed by the theories of Jean Piaget w hich underpinned that program. A short time later, I took up a study of the writin gs of Immanuel Kant and his impact upon education. In challenging Kant's notion of a p riori concepts, 'knowledge absolutely independent of all experience', I develo ped the idea of 'mental abstraction', explained then as the 'activity of th e brain/mind in matching, comparing, analyzing and synthesizing the mass of i mpressions coming in through the various sense receptors and leading to the form ation of concepts'. Piaget's 1960s theory had four factors affecting c ognitive growth. They were: (i) Nervous maturation (ii) Experience (iii) Social transmission

PAGE 38

6 of 10(iv) Equilibration That theory I refer to as the 'autonomous' model-autonomous, because growth was determined by 'equilibration', Piaget's invented term for a self-regulatory mechanism which acted to correct any disequilibrium brought about by new experiences. Equilibration also raised an individua l to higher 'stages' of cognitive growth. In struggling to apply Piaget's 1960's theories to the design of a new social studies curriculum in 1978, I came to a similar con clusion to that later reported by Lauren Resnick of the Learning Research and Develop ment Center at the University of Pittsburgh when she commented in 1983 that 'Piag etian theory provides a very weak guide for instructional efforts'. I returned to my notion of 'mental abstraction' as a likely theoretical foundation to resolve the dilemma. In developing an alternative 'supportive' model of cognitive growth, I discounted Piaget's 'stages' in favor of the idea t hat the growth is continuous, though irregular; the irregularity being influenced by fou r factors: (i) The total state of the brain and the central ne rvous system; (ii) the level and the quality of experience; (iii) the level and the quality of social interacti on; and (iv) 'sound pedagogy' (the art/craft of teaching--s omething that can be applied by a parent, a peer, or some other person, as well as the professional teacher) 'Equilibration' is no longer needed, since the pro cess of cognitive growth can be more parsimoniously explained as due to the acti vity of 'mental abstraction.' The following is a further explication of the 'sup portive' model and the four factors which influence cognitive growth: Factor (i) the total state of the brain and the central nervo us system: Rather than being looked at simply as the 'nature' aspect in the long running nature-nurture debate, the model takes into account the information being generated by brain scientists in their attempt to analyze and synthesize what happens as the billions of cells and neural connections in the brain respond to information inp uts. No one has yet made the link between input and learning, except to suggest that there is both chemical and electrical activity within the br ain in response to input. Chemical imbalance, physical or emotional trauma, f atigue, boredom, illness, prescription or other drugs, hunger and de hydration, may affect brain efficiency. Therefore 'total condition' seems to be a more adequate descriptor for what is a major variable. Piaget's maturity' factor, as presented by him in the 1960s, seems by comparison to be a less satisfactory alternative.

PAGE 39

7 of 10Factor (ii) the level and quality of experience Although concepts are generated by experience, not all experiences are of equal value. Recalling the statements of John De wey on the importance of experience, it is suggested that in t he contrived environment of the classroom teachers should select experiences largely on the criteria of quality. Factor (iii) the level and quality of social interaction In recent years there has been an increasing concen tration upon self concept as being important to effective learning. O f major importance in the development of positive self concepts are the k inds of relationships that have already developed in student personal soc ial interaction in groups, whether that might have been within the fam ily, among peers, or with children and teachers in previous classes. Factor (iv) 'sound pedagogy' (the art/craft of teaching) The dictionary defines 'pedagogy' as the 'science o r profession of teaching; also as the theory of teaching how to tea ch'. As this was the nearest to the idea of 'teaching craft', the term w as adopted as the factor which it seemed had been ignored by Piaget in his 1 960s theories on cognitive growth. It should be noted that 'sound pedagogy' consistent ly involves deliberate interventions that also involve factors (ii) and (i ii). To put it another way; sound teaching craft can, among other things, supplement personal experience and social interaction as influences on mental (cognitive) development. 'Sound pedagogy' is much more than 'instruction'. I n applying sound pedagogy the teacher's task extends beyond simply p roviding and managing experiences. The role of the teacher expan ds to include all of the following: selecting experiences using 'quality' as a measur e of appropriateness; organising, timing, monitoring and managing the e xperiences; providing order in the experiences presented (giving consideration to scope and sequence in what is presented as curri culum); attempting to reduce some of the complexity of th e material or information being presented; (The world for both children and adults is indeed complex, but if some of the complexity is reduced in presenting ideas initially, the learnings often mak e more sense when later placed back into their original complexity);

PAGE 40

8 of 10* Drawing learners into purposeful two-way communic ation; (generating a climate where learners are free to in quire, to explore issues, to formulate questions, to express ideas, t o debate points of view, and to seek solutions to problems); extending the learners' interaction with the lear ning environment (extending the range and variety of the learning co ntext). Classrooms are by nature busy places. There is such a variety of factors operating; so many things going on simultaneously; so much that is completely unpredictable; decisions to be made imme diately; events that are very public, some embarrassingly so both for students and for teachers; and each of the human elements enter with a personal background and contribute to a class history that i s completely unique. In spite of the 'busy-ness', care should be taken t o establish a climate built on concern for and a warm acceptance of each member, a classroom climate in which honesty, open-ness and m utual trust can develop. Constructivist Theory The theory that developed is essentially 'construct ivist' in nature, suggesting that we each construct our own 'reality' or 'world picture' through the processing by the brain of sensory input. The reality is dependent upon bot h the range and the quality of that sensory input--a limited experiences results in a l imited reality, a broad range of experience generates an elaborated reality. 'Constructivist' theory provides a rationale for m any of the recent innovative approaches to learning. It explains why students se em to do better through such strategies as experiential learning, inquiry learni ng, problem solving, cooperative group learning, and student-negotiated curriculum. Further, constructivism underpins the importance now being attributed in ed ucation to self-esteem and to 'metacognition.' The theory is also consistent with many of the conclusions of recent research into novice-expert representations of know ledge. (A more detailed explication of 'mental abstraction and the resultant 'constructivist' theory has been given in various p apers since first presented in 1981.) Although the theory developed from the re-think of the late 1970s it parallels the work later reported by Lauren Resnick, and the Caine and Caine publication for the Association for Supervision and Curriculum Deve lopment (ASCD). Several quotes will suffice: The human mind has been rediscovered, or at least r e-affirmed; reasoning and thought are central objects of scient ific study ... It seems evident that a cognitive theory of instruction shou ld be emerging alongside our increasingly elaborated theories of c ognitive performance and development. Lauren Resnick (1983)

PAGE 41

9 of 10Brain research establishes and confirms that multip le complex and concrete experiences are essential for meaningful l earning and teaching. Optimizing the use of the human brain mea ns using the brain's infinite capacity to make connections and understanding what conditions maximize this process. Caine and Caine (1990)Reinforcement for the direction taken was accepted to come from a further Resnick statement: It now seems absolutely certain that our task is to develop a theory of intervention that places the learner's active menta l construction at the very heart of the instructional exchange. In a recent yearbook of the ASCD, Cawelti makes th e comment that the most critical ingredient of successful schools is the te acher and the quality of the teaching in the classroom. Referring briefly to the dominanc e of behaviorists over the past several decades, he draws attention to the chapter by Peterson and Knapp. In Cawelti's words: They record the important work of the 'constructivi sts' who are seeking to demonstrate how students must be helped to creat e their own meaning out of the learning experiences the school provides. He adds a further comment: The constructivist movement in learning will do muc h to help get students more involved, particularly if students ca n be helped to see that in adult life they will need to know what they are being asked to learn. The 'Logical Sequential' Model of Curriculum Design and Development From the outset, I had accepted social studies to i nclude aspects of anthropology, economics, politics, natural and applied sciences, as well as history and geography, and set the following objectives: The curriculum should: emphasize the need for children to develop an und erstanding of self, the relationship of self to others, and from that a n understanding of society; provide a structure of scope and sequence from Ki ndergarten to Year-six; present a core of suggested experiences and learn ings in social studies Y-K through Y-6; provide children with quality experiences; position the experiences and concepts over the se ven year period based on an appropriate theory of cognitive growth;

PAGE 42

10 of 10give weighting to both content and process; allow experiences and concepts to be interrelated within the structure; be constructed of selected categories of social s tudies rising as expanding experience spirals, providing later reinf orcement for earlier experiences; give prominence to the ideas developed at a semin ar in 1976 with Professor Jack Fraenkel of San Francisco concerning an education in values. When published as a research document in 1981, the Humanities Core Curriculum (HCC) fold-out chart was extremely well received by teach ers, administrators, parents and academics in all States of Australia. Visitors from overseas and representatives of national publishers also showed considerable interest. The HCC Chart and the handbook are an outcome of a pplying the "Logical Sequential Model" to the design of curriculum. [then followed a statement explaining how the curri culum was applied in developing class programs] ************************* The need to shift theory and practice is becoming m ore apparent as schools move to include convergent communications and information t echnologies in their delivery of curriculum. During the past four years, I have been working wi th colleagues on a series of investigations for governments in Australia into th e application of state-of-the-art technologies in the delivery of education at all le vels, from schools to universities. The findings recorded in three major reports endors e the importance of the shift to constructivism made both by educators at the leadin g edge and the instructional designers responsible for developing quality educat ional software in opening up a future of new learning opportunities.

PAGE 43

1 of 1 Contributed Commentary on Volume 4 Number 8: Stone Developmentalism: An Obscure but Pervasive Restrict ion on Educational Improvement 2 May 1996John StoneSTONEJ@EDUSERV.EAST-TENN-ST.EDU On May 2, 1996 (#2) Sherman Dorn wrote: Educational researchers conduct surveys of principa ls and teachers all the time about such things, and it seems to me one could try to have a *rough* gauge of such influence. Having evidence of its influence back to the 1960s is what I doubt one could have. But that is what Stone is suggesting, a nd I doubt it is true. When reasonable people differ on questions like this, an ecdotes are insufficient. One needs detailed case studies or broader evidence. I will see if I can find some survey evidence. Sur prisingly, I think I can produce a great deal in the way of neoprogressive exponents of deve lopmentalism. The 1962 ASCD Yearbook "Perceiving, Behaving, and Becoming featured Abe Ma slow, Earl Kelly, Art Combs, and Carl Rogers-all claiming that the central purpose of s chooling was the personal (i.e., psychological) development of the student. The 1972 ASCD yearbook edited by J.R. Squire is titled "A New Look at Progressive Education." It favored many of the same authors and presented approvingly most of the developmentalist concepts that underpin ned the then discredited progressive education movement.

PAGE 44

1 of 2 Contributed Commentary on Volume 4 Number 8: Stone Developmentalism: An Obscure but Pervasive Restrict ion on Educational Improvement 2 May 1996John StoneSTONEJ@EDUSERV.EAST-TENN-ST.EDU Sherman Dorn writes: I would also bet that many people who use developme ntalism as an *excuse* not to change teaching methods are doing so, at least in p art, for other reasons. Intense instruction, even to small groups of students, is e ven more exhausting than poor teaching. I agree with you entirely. Although I have not car efully examined this hypothesis, I suspect developmentalism may be appealing for econo mic reasons. So long as teaching is a matter of fitting instruction to highly individuali zed developmental patterns and the danger of inappropriate intervention is great, teaching is bo und to require lots of teachers and take lots of time. Also if intangible developmental limitations bar progress, teacher accountability measures must be questioned. As to your point about the work involved in intens ive instruction and for that matter, the work in learning research based modes of instructio n, there is no question that resistance on such grounds does exist. However, I must hasten to say t hat there is very little to encourage teachers to work hard and to insure learning because achievemen t outcomes are typically given so little attention. As to published reports of intervention oriented pr ograms discarded or rejected on account of differences with what seems to be develo pmentalist thinking, I can refer you to the following off the top of my head: Thanks for posting these. I will see if I can locate more. I'm confident the y exist. On the influence of Dewey: As to Cremin's account of progressive education, it is reasonable to contend that the Progressive Education Association did lose connecti on with Dewey's philosophy... That the Association changed is one thing, that "pr ogressive education" changed is another. The criticism of progressive education after WWII w as focused on the PEA and the Life Adjustment Movement -most incisively (as in Arthur Bestor) the curriculum of

PAGE 45

2 of 2high schools. I've read Bestor, and I don't recall where developmental psychology was an issue, either explicitly or implicitly. I agree with your understanding of Bestor's critiq ue and you are right that the life adjustment movement was not explicitly premised on developmental psychology. In my view, however, that which Bestor found objectionable was consistent with the developmentalist thinking that had been inherent in the progressive education movement since its earliest days. Marietta Johnson, for example, had been greatly inf luenced by developmental ideas in her formulation of the Organic School and much of her t hinking entered into the early expression of principles by the PEA. A key idea was that educatio n cannot stress only the intellectual aspects of growing and developing without doing violence to th e other areas. The idea of educating the "whole child" was, thus, a centerpiece of progressi ve thinking throughout the twenties and thirties and much of the life adjustment concept se ems entirely consistent. For example, the 1948 Commission for Life Adjustment Education for Youth described life adjustment education (in part): "It is concerned with ethical and moral livi ng and with physical, mental, and emotional health." Bestor's criticism of this kind of thinkin g (in a 1953 New Republic article) was that schools have a far narrower and more intellectual m ission and that church, home, and other institutions and agencies should minister to the ot her needs of youth. "The idea that the school must undertake to meet every need that some other a gency is failing to meet is a preposterous delusion that can wreck the educational system with out contributing anything to the salvation of society." More relevant to the matter of doctrine and the ide as imported to the schools are the progressive and neo progressive nature of therecomm endations about sound teaching practice issued by the National Education Association and the U. S. Office of Education (also by the U. S. Bureau of Education ). I would take this with a grain of salt, sort of lik e the mothering recommendations put out by the Child Bureau (or, later, Spock). Som e portion of the population saw them as bibles, but they're not evidence of actual childrearing practice or even widespread philosophies. I agree that the fact of such recommendations are not the same thing as observed practices and as I mentioned in my reply to Rick (and some ot hers, off-list), my thesis is not that developmentalist practices such as progressive educ ation have thoroughly captivated the schools. Rather my thesis is that the developmentalist premi ses have served to encourage the adoption of a variety of practices that are consistent with suc h thinking and, moreover, that they have discouraged the adoption of practices that seem to have high promise of effectiveness. Thanks again for your thoughtful commentary.

PAGE 46

1 of 1 Contributed Commentary on Volume 4 Number 8: Stone Developmentalism: An Obscure but Pervasive Restrict ion on Educational Improvement 2 May 1996Sherman Dorndornsj@CTRVAX.VANDERBILT.EDU On April 30, 1996 Rick Garlikov wrote: It is very difficult to give evidence of a pervasiv e but unconscious attitude in a field. Educational researchers conduct surveys of princip als and teachers all the time about such things, and it seems to me one could try to have a rough gauge of such influence. Having evidence of its influence back to the 1960s is what I doubt one could have. But that is what Stone is suggesting, and I doubt it is true. When reasona ble people differ on questions like this, anecdotes are insufficient. One needs detailed case studies or broader evidence. Rick Garlikov writes: I thought that what J.E. Stone said "fit" many of t he teachers I know who DO adhere to some of the pedagogical philosophies that he cal ls "developmentalist." Yes, and it agrees with my impressions of some tea chers, too. However, that is not nearly as persuasive an explanation of resistance as other more mundane, and more widespread forces. I thought the paper was important, but it is diffic ult to characterize what "kind" of scholarship effort it represents if one is into suc h categorizing. Still I think it was a good, worthwhile, and scholarly article. Oh, I think so, too, and I will certainly recommen d it to students alongside other works about resistance of teachers to change. One does no t have to think a work is unscholarly to disagree with it.

PAGE 47

1 of 2 Contributed Commentary on Volume 4 Number 8: Stone Developmentalism: An Obscure but Pervasive Restrict ion on Educational Improvement 2 May 1996Sherman Dorndornsj@CTRVAX.VANDERBILT.EDU J. E. Stone writes: I agree that the present paper offers no empirical evidence of developmentalism as a barrier. My primary aim was to bring into focus a p henomenon that, in my view, pervades education in such a way that it has verita bly become part of the air we breathe. I have named it and sought to show its edu cational significance. I think it's provocative and a plausible thesis an d, as I wrote Rick, I will suggest people read it. However, I'm more cautious about it, becau se resistance to change is more widespread than the people who adhere to what you call develop mentalist philosophies. I would also bet that many people who use developmentalism as an *excuse* not to change teaching methods are doing so, at least in part, for other reasons. Inte nse instruction, even to small groups of students, is even more exhausting than poor teaching. As to published reports of intervention oriented pr ograms discarded or rejected on account of differences with what seems to be develo pmentalist thinking, I can refer you to the following off the top of my head: Thanks for posting these. You may want to use this type of evidence in future articles. It would be more persuasive (at least to me) than citi ng methods textbooks. On the influence of Dewey: As to Cremin's account of progressive education, it is reasonable to contend that the Progressive Education Association did lose connecti on with Dewey's philosophy... That the Association changed is one thing, that "pr ogressive education" changed is another. The criticism of progressive education after WWII was focused on the PEA and the Life Adjustment Movement -most incisively (as in Arthu r Bestor) the curriculum of high schools. I've read Bestor, and I don't recall where developm ental psychology was an issue, either explicitly or implicitly. More relevant to the matter of doctrine and the ide as imported to the schools are the progressive and neo progressive nature of the recom mendations about sound

PAGE 48

2 of 2teaching practice issued by the National Education Association and the U. S. Office of Education (also by the U. S. Bureau of Education ). I would take this with a grain of salt, sort of li ke the mothering recommendations put out by the Child Bureau (or, later, Spock). Some portio n of the population saw them as bibles, but they're not evidence of actual childrearing practic e or even widespread philosophies.

PAGE 49

1 of 2 Contributed Commentary on Volume 4 Number 8: Stone Developmentalism: An Obscure but Pervasive Restrict ion on Educational Improvement 1 May 1996Larry Phillipsljp@GPU.SRV.UALBERTA.CA I think the discussion of Stone's paper misses som e important considerations. I don't think resistance to change has anything to do with "isms" It has to do with people and what asking them to change means to them. The following is an e xcerpt from a reflective essay I wrote after shadowing several principals. It is a bit long. For those who want the essence in 25 words or less. Change requires: a perceived need an effective alternative the resources to implement it Effecting Change in Schools: School are About Peopl e: My last two school visits were to schools where ch ange was causing or had caused conflict. The visits brought home the notion that s chools are about people and that bringing about change in schools is bringing about change in peopl e. I was also reminded that the people we want to change may resent being told they can do be tter. Then there is the part that really hurts, perhaps what is being done is best for the school a nd shouldn't be changed. The corollary is there are times the students don't and shouldn't come fir st. There are times when it is important for the schoo l and hence the students to give teachers time to change even when you are sure the needs of students currently in the classes aren't being met. Today's student is disadvantaged to benefit to morrows. In one school, changes in instructional methods had been put on hold. Change had been imposed on the teachers and been resisted. During this respite, the students are in a structured environment. This may or may not be what the students need, but it is what the teachers need, immersion in a comfortable, familiar environment to gather the confidence to face change The other school had a teacher who was experiencin g difficulty. The principal was working with the teacher to overcome these problems In the meantime the students don't have a teacher with a full range of competencies. If teach ers are going to acknowledge their weaknesses and provide an opportunity to overcome them, they m ust be confident that they will be treated fairly. In many cases this involves remaining in th e classroom, while acquiring new skills. Demonstrated fairness is needed to make substantial changes to how teachers work together and instructional approaches. A significant change will involve giving up an approach that has been mastered and is familiar and learning a new skill. There needs to be assurance that time will be given to learn the skill and help will be provided so the teacher can gain a new competency to replace the one abandoned. If teachers aren't confi dent of their abilities or are unsure of expectations they may resist change even when it do esn't directly affect them.

PAGE 50

2 of 2 Because of the high personal cost and risk, change isn't adopted lightly. To have a teacher change instructional approaches, three conditions m ust be met. First the teacher has to believe the change is necessary. Second the teacher has to be c onfident enough to attempt the change and third, the teacher has to believe the new approach will be effective. To establish a desire for change in instructional methods teachers must recognize a need for change. Most teachers care about their students and use teaching methods they feel are best for them. Suggesting that student needs are not bei ng met is a comment on the teacher's competency. If the class isn't performing well the teacher will probably be seeking help, but if the class is doing reasonably well establishing the val ue of change will be more difficult. This can be done in two ways, both of which rely on the profess ional ethics of the teacher. If there is an identifiable group of students who aren't doing wel l, the teacher can be asked to develop a strategy to meet those students' needs. The other a pproach is to examine the curriculum and compare the requirements to student learning. Defic iencies are reason to ask for changes in approach. Allowing the teacher to try to meet these needs using existing techniques establishes the need for a different approach in the teacher's mind. If the student needs can be met with current approaches, you have to ask yourself why ch ange is needed. Confidence to attempt change comes from respect, s elf respect and the respect of others. The approach to establishing a need for change resp ects the teachers skills and integrity. The change isn't being suggested because of lack of com petence, the change is being made because expectations have been changed. Involving the teach er in defining the need and suggesting an approach to meet the need recognizes and respects t he teacher's competence. If the teacher has identified the approach as a be tter way to meet student needs, technical effectiveness has been established. To believe that the approach is practical the teacher needs to know that professional development opportunities ar e available to gain the required competencies. The teacher will also need assurance that curricular and other resources will be available to enable success. Finally the teacher wi ll want to know that parents and the community will support the change. Which brings up a sticky point. The teacher isn't alone in the classroom and the school isn't alone in the community. We looked at gaining the support of the teacher first, because it is a necessary condition for change. If the teacher does n't support the change it won't happen. The parents need to understand the change and why it is being made. They will need to know that their child's learning will not be harmed and that learning can be demonstrated. Parental support gives the teacher confidence, a third party thinks the approach is reasonable. The parents can also protect the program from outside interference, sinc e the principal can point to the parents and say they won't support altering the program. The group that never gets asked is the students. They should be involved because they have to live with t he changes. In some schools students are made aware of the curricular expectations, but I ha ve never seen a situation were students are asked how they would like to be taught. I suspect i t is because deep down we know we won't like the answer. . . . . . . . Need can be demonstrated in a number of ways. Prin cipals can use professional development create a desire for change. Professiona l development provides an opportunity to see and explore other ways of doing things. These are i mportant for the changes that don't directly affect student performance, but are just better way s of working together. Request from the community and survey results can lead to an examina tion of practice. Assessment results can be used to show a need for reorganizing the school a s well as changing instructional practice. This is particularly true if the assessment is broadened to cover all of the curricular requirements.

PAGE 51

1 of 1 Contributed Commentary on Volume 4 Number 8: Stone Developmentalism: An Obscure but Pervasive Restrict ion on Educational Improvement 30 April 1996Aimee Howleyhowley@MARSHALL.EDU On April 30, 1996 Benjamin Levin wrote: Sherman Dorn's comments on Stone's paper are very a ppropriate. We've heard a great deal about the baneful influence of progressi vism on educational outcomes, but all the studies of classrooms continue to show the vast prevalence of traditional teaching techniques teachers talk, kids sit and l isten or write notes or do seat work. I wish Dewey had had as much impact as his critics say he did! The prevalence of traditional methods may suggest that developmentalism doesn't have an important effect on resilient practices, but it doe sn't adequately counter the claim that developmentalism serves as a rhetorical impediment to certain other practices. Acceleration of bright students provides a case in point. Despite r ather convincing evidence of the benefit of this practice, teachers and administrators routinely dis allow it. The most typical reason given is that acceleration will interfere with the healthy social and emotional development of bright students. Educators invoke the "whole child" argument as a wa y to keep from engaging in an educational practice that they find unacceptable. Having dealt with this argument again and again, I am convinced that, no matter how misdirected the argum ent may be, educators usually are committed to it out of an earnest regard for studen ts' well-being. Here, an ethos of developmentalism restricts educators' consideration of reasonable alternatives. I do not think that in most cases the argument is offered cynically or in a calculative manner.

PAGE 52

1 of 1 Contributed Commentary on Volume 4 Number 8: Stone Developmentalism: An Obscure but Pervasive Restrict ion on Educational Improvement 30 April 1996Rick Garlikovhmwkhelp@SCOTT.NET It is very difficult to give evidence of a pervasi ve but unconscious attitude in a field. I thought that what J.E. Stone said "fit" many of the teachers I know who DO adhere to some of the pedagogical philosophies that he calls "develop mentalist". I would be hardpressed to prove empirically it fits, but that is in part because wh en you spell it out as he does, they tend to deny having that view. Yet many of the things they say l ogically lead to it. I thought the paper was important, but it is diffi cult to characterize what "kind" of scholarship effort it represents if one is into suc h categorizing. Still I think it was a good, worthwhile, and scholarly article; and I think (as the letter in his post exemplified) that it in some sense explains the resistance of many developmental ists to other sorts of methods --and it explains it to people who have presented such empir ically based methods and been rejected in ways that did not make sense to them at the time, b ut which make sense (or are consistent with) Prof. Stone's analysis/characterization.

PAGE 53

1 of 4 Contributed Commentary on Volume 4 Number 8: Stone Developmentalism: An Obscure but Pervasive Restrict ion on Educational Improvement 30 April 1996John StoneSTONEJ@EDUSERV.EAST-TENN-ST.EDU Sherman, Thanks for posting a reaction. My hope had been to stimulate some thought about developmentalism as one piece of the puzzle about h ow and why it is so difficult to improve educational outcomes. In the following, I will try to respond to your several points. On April 29, 1996 Sherman writes: Like Rick Garlikov, I found it appealing in the sen se that I have witnessed some of the dynamics which Stone claims dominates teaching. Yet ultimately I find the article unconvincing for several reasons. 1. In an article which espouses empiricism, Stone pre sents remarkably little concrete evidence that developmentalist philosophy is a prim ary barrier to more effective teaching. The following are two generalizations whi ch would need evidence to convince me of Stone's thesis: (a) Developmentalism has been important to teachers since the late 1960s (when, if I recall correctly, the first studi es of Direct Instruction and other quasi-experimental intervention programs were published). (b) Developmentalism has been a barrier to the use of research-based interventions: (1) A developmentalist philosophy has blocked the implementation of research-based intervention progr ams in specific locations; or (2) A substantial number of teachers across the cou ntry have considered research-based intervention program s and have discarded them explicitly because of developme ntalist principles. Evidence of these is nonexistent in the article. In stead, Stone presents what some teacher education texts say about teachin g, and what some constructivist researchers have said about specific teaching methods (or about reinforcement in general) -which reflect on *those texts* but which says little either about teacher education in general or about how

PAGE 54

2 of 4teachers make decisions in classrooms. I agree that the present paper offers no empirical evidence of developmentalism as a barrier. My primary aim was t o bring into focus a phenomenon that, in my view, pervades education in such a way that it has veritably become part of the air we breathe. I have named it and sought to show its educational significance. As to evidence of its exi stence or studies showing how it has served as a barrier, I would hope that individu als who have attempted to implement various experimentally demonstrated inter ventions might assess their experiences in light of this report. Happily, one such a assessment came to my attentio n yesterday. The following is a quote from an educational researcher who has been attempting to implement technological improvements: Prof. Stone:Your recent article on Developmentalism is an excel lent and instructive contribution. I have circulated it to many of my co lleagues who must confront these questions daily. Would you please al so send other of your reprints that relate to the general topic? We have worked for several years on the Florida Sch oolyear 2000 Initiative, the intention of which is to redesign p ublic education in Florida. We find it a daunting task, for all the re asons that you cited. As to published reports of intervention oriented p rograms discarded or rejected on account of differences with what seems to be developmentalist thinking, I can refer you to the following off the top of my head: Binder and Watkins (1989) Promoting effective instr uctional methods. FUTURE CHOICES 1(3), 33-39. If I recall correctly, Binder and Watkins make ref erence to a "developmentalist bias" in the thinking of school p ersonnel. Watkins (1988, July) Project Follow Through: A stor y of the identification and neglect of effective instruction. YOUTH POLICY, pp. 7-11. Herbert Walberg at U of IL Chicago has written a n umber of pieces on the rejection and disuse of experimentally grounded int erventions, notably those employing a mastery learning approach. Sherman writes: 2. Others are more persuasive in explaining why teach ers don't change their methods much. Larry Cuban and Seymour Sarason have each argued that teaching is innately conservative and t hat schools create a conservative work culture. The most common teaching methods, especially in secondary schools, have changed relat ively little over the past century compared to more experimental models w hich have existed side-by-side with more "traditional" classes. In *e very single case*, traditional classes are more influential on the nex t generation of teachers and on teachers asked to change. It hasn't really mattered whether those experimental models were the Lab Scho ol run by Dewey

PAGE 55

3 of 4or DISTAR, the Eight-Year project of the NEA or som ething else. Schools and teachers just have not picked up on new methods easily or faithfully. It does not require the inculcation of constructivism to have continued that pattern in the last few decades. I do not disagree with the observation that school s employ traditional methods and are generally reluctant to adopt new ap proaches. As I indicated yesterday in my reply to Rick Garlikov, I find teac her attitudes entirely understandable. Teachers have to deal with classroo m reality on a daily basis and, in my opinion, it is the realities of this environment shapes their practices. Much of that which they are taught by schools of education or in the context of inservice training has not been well tested. Also much of what they ar e expected to implement--even in those cases where the ideas are workable--is not co mpatible with funding patterns or other organizational arrangements. Teachers are fre quently given a brief introduction and left to fend for themselves. In an environment in which there is no particular premium on consistently high educational outcomes a nd given the dearth of realistic (cost-effective and labor saving) advice about how to change, teachers stick with that which they are familiar--but with one critical cave at: the strictures posed by developmentalism. Developmentalism in its many incarnations has, in my opinion, succeeded in restricting the practices that teachers consider to be acceptable. For example, teachers believe that motivation to learn must stem from interest; that pressure, demands, and expectations for performance are apt t o be harmful; and that punishment is to be avoided. Broadly speaking, my p oint is not that developmentalism has influenced the schools through the widespread adoption of progressive, constructivist, or other such programs Rather, I contend that in setting informal but virtually inviolable strictures on tea ching practice, developmentalism has impeded the adoption of effective practices. Sherman writes: 3. Stone's chronology implies that Dewey and other "d evelopmentalists" were far more influential on educators than they ac tually were. As Ellen Lagemann wrote in Teachers College Record several y ears ago, Thorndike won the battle of educational philosophie s in the early twentieth century. Dewey essentially lost, and it w asn't until decades later that someone else (and you can argue whether it was Piaget, Robert Coles, or others) became an effective rhetor ical advocate of treating children as having mental lives of their o wn. Stone cites Lawrence Cremin's history of progressivism but omit s a key message: while becoming a dominant professional force, the P rogressive Education Association lost virtually every connecti on it had with Dewey's educational philosophy -including, critic ally, the parts of Dewey which Stone identifies as developmentalist. Similarly, I have my doubts about the reaches of co nstructivism. Visible in many schools of education, sure. Identifiable am ong individual teachers and principals, absolutely. But right next to constructivists you'll find other teachers who may fail their stude nts *just as much* as constructivists and refuse to change even more. I am aware of Lagemann' view, but I am not sure sh e takes into account the kind of strictures I believe result from Dewey's th inking.

PAGE 56

4 of 4 As to Cremin's account of progressive education, i t is reasonable to contend that the Progressive Education Association did lose connection with Dewey's philosophy--Counts' "Dare Progressive Education be Progressive" speech in 1932 being a watershed event (actually, of course, Count s' views were never adopted). That the Association changed is one thing, that "pr ogressive education" changed is another. Citing Cremin: Pondering the relationship between the PEA and progressive education and like pondering the relati onship between religion and a church or between ideology and a political party. T he PEA changed, but did "progressive education?" More relevant to the matter of doctrine and the id eas imported to the schools are the progressive and neo progressive nature of t he recommendations about sound teaching practice issued by the National Education Association and the U. S. Office of Education (also by the U. S. Bureau of Education ). Although not developmentalist in the Rousseauian sense (in later years), they wer e clearly premised on what I have termed Dewey's interactionist form of developmental ism. One could argue that Rousseauian views went into eclipse (only to reemer ge in the late sixties), but the "developmentalism" to which I refer is a broader do ctrine. Again, thanks for your comments.

PAGE 57

1 of 1 Contributed Commentary on Volume 4 Number 8: Stone Developmentalism: An Obscure but Pervasive Restrict ion on Educational Improvement 30 April 1996Benjamin Levinlevin@CC.UMANITOBA.CA Sherman Dorn's comments on Stone's paper are very appropriate. We've heard a great deal about the baneful influence of progressivism on edu cational outcomes, but all the studies of classrooms continue to show the vast prevalence of traditional teaching techniques teachers talk, kids sit and listen or write notes or do seat work. I wish Dewey had had as much impact as his critics say he did!

PAGE 58

1 of 2 Contributed Commentary on Volume 4 Number 8: Stone Developmentalism: An Obscure but Pervasive Restrict ion on Educational Improvement 29 April 1996Sherman Dorndornsj@CTRVAX.VANDERBILT.EDU In general, I found Stone's paper, arguing that a philosophy of developmentalism blocks many teachers from using effective teaching methods provocative and interesting. Like Rick Garlikov, I found it appealing in the sense that I have witnessed some of the dynamics which Stone claims dominates teaching. Yet ultimately I find the article unconvincing for several reasons. 1. In an article which espouses empiricism, Stone pre sents remarkably little concrete evidence that developmentalist philosophy is a primary barri er to more effective teaching. The following are two generalizations which would need evidence t o convince me of Stone's thesis: (a) Developmentalism has been important to teachers since the late 1960s (when, if I recall correctly, the first studies of Direct Instr uction and other quasi-experimental intervention programs were published). (b) Developmentalism has been a barrier to the use of research-based interventions: (1) A developmentalist philosophy has blocked the i mplementation of research-based intervention programs in specific lo cations; or (2) A substantial number of teachers across the cou ntry have considered research-based intervention programs and have disca rded them explicitly because of developmentalist principles. Evidence of these is nonexistent in the article. I nstead, Stone presents what some teacher education texts say about teaching, and what some c onstructivist researchers have said about specific teaching methods (or about reinforcement i n general) -which reflect on *those texts* but which says little either about teacher educatio n in general or about how teachers make decisions in classrooms.2. Others are more persuasive in explaining why teach ers don't change their methods much. Larry Cuban and Seymour Sarason have each argued that tea ching is innately conservative and that schools create a conservative work culture. The mos t common teaching methods, especially in secondary schools, have changed relatively little o ver the past century compared to more experimental models which have existed side-by-side with more "traditional" classes. In *every single case*, traditional classes are more influent ial on the next generation of teachers and on teachers asked to change. It hasn't really mattered whether those experimental models were the

PAGE 59

2 of 2Lab School run by Dewey or DISTAR, the Eight-Year p roject of the NEA or something else. Schools and teachers just have not picked up on new methods easily or faithfully. It does not require the inculcation of constructivism to have c ontinued that pattern in the last few decades. 3. Stone's chronology implies that Dewey and other "d evelopmentalists" were far more influential on educators than they actually were. A s Ellen Lagemann wrote in Teachers College Record several years ago, Thorndike won the battle of educational philosophies in the early twentieth century. Dewey essentially lost, and it w asn't until decades later that someone else (and you can argue whether it was Piaget, Robert Coles, or others) became an effective rhetorical advocate of treating children as having mental live s of their own. Stone cites Lawrence Cremin's history of progressivism but omits a key message: w hile becoming a dominant professional force, the Progressive Education Association lost virtuall y every connection it had with Dewey's educational philosophy -including, critically, th e parts of Dewey which Stone identifies as developmentalist. Similarly, I have my doubts about the reaches of c onstructivism. Visible in many schools of education, sure. Identifiable among individual t eachers and principals, absolutely. But right next to constructivists you'll find other teachers who may fail their students *just as much* as constructivists and refuse to change even more. I am not denying here either the dangers of not in tervening in failing educational dynamics or the real contradictions in Dewey's or Piaget's p hilosophy. But one must put it in perspective.

PAGE 60

1 of 5 Contributed Commentary on Volume 4 Number 8: Stone Developmentalism: An Obscure but Pervasive Restrict ion on Educational Improvement 29 April 1996John StoneSTONEJ@EDUSERV.EAST-TENN-ST.EDU Rick, thanks for your very thoughtful analysis of my recent EPAA article on "developmentalism." It would have been advantageous to see your thinking while I was reviewing and revising. I won't be able to address your concerns as thoroughly as they deserve in this post, but let me begin by making 2 points: As you say in your last paragraph, "I believe that it is not age development that generally creates readiness, but development through meaningf ul exposure or experience." In general, I agree and I wrote about developmentalism in an atte mpt to counter what I see as a widely assumed (not necessarily well understood) doctrinal limitation on how educators go about improving their practices. Please bear in mind that my principal objective wa s the relatively narrow one of trying to identify and describe a set of assumptions about learning and the nature of human development and to show that they have considerable educational importance. Obviously, my account has numerous implications for educational ( and parenting) practice--chief among which is the matter of how experimental research is used and what that has to do with more effective schooling. A more complete treatment of how and whe re developmentalist assumptions intersect with social and educational issues would require mu ch lengthier treatment. In the following, I will try to respond briefly to a number of your points: (1) does not sufficiently explain or take into acco unt the rationales, and philosophical points, of other people for some of t he approaches he refers to as "developmental" I agree. Much more could be said but I was only tr ying to show that they intersect and likely implications. (2) My chief concern in writing this is that the go od aspects of some of the approaches Prof. Stone considers "developmental" no t be thrown out with those elements he effectively argues are bad. I too would not want to banish everything associat ed with those approaches identified as developmental. I say, let's look at evidence of eff ectiveness. 3. ...the purpose of school is to give students a b roader range of knowledge and skills than whatever the workplace may likely demand... (s nip) ...where schools do not teach well enough to adequately prepare students fo r the workplace, that signifies a

PAGE 61

2 of 5problem on my view only because that should be a mi nimal outcome of the sort of education I seek for students. I agree that meeting the demands of the workplace is a minimum and I too would want schools to go well beyond. However, it is well to b ear in mind that it is failure to meet the minimum that has critical personal, social and econ omic implications, and that failure to meet this minimum is a matter of central concern to the people who are paying most of us to teach. I think if the many surveys of public opinion in the matter of educational objectives tell us anything, they say to public elementary and seconda ry schools: First and foremost, do a vastly better job of insuring that everyone has the litera cy, numeracy, communication, etc. skills necessary to the workplace (and necessary to prepar edness for postsecondary learning) in the information age. (4) ...teachers (like anyone else) are disposed to favor specific practices with which they are familiar and comfortable -frequently tea ching as they have been taught, rather than teaching as they have been taught to te ach in ed schools. Having spent a career in teacher education, I will be the first to agree with the point that teachers make only limited use of that which they h ave been taught in the colleges of education. However, the truth of that assertion does not mean that teacher education (and its doctrines) is having no effect. Rather, in my judgement, teacher training has a substantial restrictive effect. What I have observed and learned from the relevant literature (surveys of teachers, etc.) is that teachers frequently find that that which they are t aught in the colleges of education does not work in the classroom. For this reason, a perennial refo rm in teacher education is more apprenticeship type training and less time spent on theory and met hods. A companion reform in TN has been to require education professors to spend so many days per year in the schools. I teach the required developmental psychology courses (for teachers and non teachers), and teacher surveys find that such courses are among the most inapplicable. Confronted with the daily reality of having to fin d something that does work, teachers use the kind of teaching that enabled them personally t o learn; they rely on that which other teachers have found to work; and they rely on that which see ms to work with their students. For lack of any better information, they are forced to continua lly "reinvent the wheel" (i.e., innovate) and over the years the same innovations and the same fa ulty initiatives (uncharitably called "fads") come around again and again--all at student and tax payer expense. In my opinion, teacher training further contribute s to this situation by a) failing to train prospective teachers in any experimentally vindicat ed approaches to teaching (that might be used or adapted) or by b) affording such little training in a given approach that implementation is almost bound to fail. From what I have seen over th e years, well demonstrated teaching practices have been neglected or abandoned because (inadequat ely trained teachers) could not make them work (after having a few classes or a workshop). Ov er time, most teachers become so jaded about the latest "innovation" that they understandably ig nore new ideas regardless of merit. Finally, developmentalist teacher training effecti vely encourages teachers to believe that good teaching requires whatever approach they devis e to be, first and foremost, well received by students and, second, effective in producing academ ic achievement. This order of priorities is more or less the reverse of the public's. Schools t hat fail to produce acceptable degrees of conventional academic achievement are nonsense to t he public. It is my suspicion that this stricture combined with the uncertainty about wheth er an untested innovation will produce results markedly limits that which teachers and sch ools are willing to attempt with students. In other words, there is a boundary based on doctrine and effectively reorders educational priorities. I might add that this is a terribly expensive way t o go about education. Teachers are sent on a perpetual quest for the perfect fit between teachin g practice and the individual student's

PAGE 62

3 of 5developmental attributes on the theory that an exce llent fit will be both well received and successful. Again, in my opinion, the public would prefer schooling that succeeds in producing learning whether or not students find it entirely t o their tastes. (5) ...there being grounds besides "natural develop ment" for advocating methods other than those research has shown effective I do not disagree. My point is that the "natural" attribute is important to the appeal of these approaches, perhaps a critically important attribut e. Neither am I arguing that all traditional or unnatural approaches are effective. (6) The first problem is that there is much publish ed which seems quite clearly to be flawed research, or interpretations of research, in that it does not isolate an independent variable and show its effect. Yes, there is plenty of flawed research--experimen tal and otherwise; and yes, it is difficult to isolate the effects of independent variables in complex situations. However, I do not take these considerable difficulties as arguments for abandoni ng experiments. Instead, I ask whether there is better avenue to credible knowledge of teaching eff ectiveness. It seems to me that teacher education and the teac hing profession generally has some obligation to assure that the skills with which tea chers are equipped actually work. I think the obligation is largely parallel to that had by medic al schools and the medical profession. Experimentally validated and field tested findings have enabled enormous advancements in medicine and many other areas of human endeavor. Th at they would fail so completely in education would be odd indeed. My point here is that if the teaching profession h as an obligation to equip teachers with practices that work and that experiments are the be st way of making such a determination, then experimental evidence should play a prominent role in our thinking about how to teach. If we reject experimentation on the grounds that it is le ss than perfect, it seems to an unfair comparison--the perfect hypothetical is made the en emy of the best real option. (7)*IF* you can make the practice fun, is that not better than making drill tedious --if you achieve the same learning. Not better because i t is more effective in the short run, but because it may be more effective in the lo ng run for students' schooling in general, and is more humane. I am not against memor ization, nor am I against drill. The argument is over the specifics and the outcomes with regard to a reasonable span of time. If you teach kids to read, but make t hem hate to read, what of value have you accomplished? I wholly favor making learning fun and interesting and if students generally learned the way Rousseau's Emile did, for example, the educatio nal issues that concern us would be largely nonexistent. It is worth remembering, however, that Rousseau's real children were shipped off to an orphanage. The point I am making is that in those cases where teachers find something that "clicks" with the student, the resulting learning can be ide al. Your personal examples are great; and to all who can find similarly thoughtful and creative ways of achieving results, I offer my complements. The great problem of education, howeve r, is what to do about the very substantial numbers of students who do not respond. My question is: Must teachers be limited to method s that are immediately gratifying and well received by students? I am suggesting that dev elopmentalism, in effect, sets such a limit. As would be true of any reasonable and humane individu al, I favor the most gratifying methods we

PAGE 63

4 of 5can devise and I certainly would exclude interventi on that goes beyond the bounds of decent and humane treatment. Where I probably would part compa ny with many members of the teaching profession, however, is that I would balance the pr ivations attendant a student's effort during his or her school years against the catastrophic prospe ct of failure to learn. Learning takes study (defined broadly) and study takes time and effort. Almost inevitably in our day and age, study time comes at the expense of some far more attracti ve activities. Either children discipline themselves to the task as a result of the enthusias m inspired by their teacher or the teacher (and the parent) somehow insure that the necessary time and effort is allocated. To me, letting children become much less than they can be is truly abusive. Another area in which I would part company with ma ny teachers and teacher educators is in the matter of how patient we should be in expect ing students to progress. I think that individuals whom I would term developmentalists see time and expected progress as largely open ended. My view is that time is money and there are finite limits to both. Schools are enormously expensive. When college level remedial programs hav e to re-teach basic skills to high school graduates (even ones with above average GPAs), I th ink we need to take a careful look at whether students are making good use of the educati onal opportunity they are provided. Schooling is plenty expensive even without waste. P ermitting students to advance without learning wastes their time as well as the taxpayer' s money. What we know as adults is that there is only a brief period in one's life when one's par ents provide a place to live and pay the bills. Sooner or later most people are on their own; and a s many of the students I see every day will tell you, they wished their parents and their teachers h ad pushed them while the opportunity was there. In addition to believing that many in teaching fai l to balance present deprivation and discomfort against the catastrophic effects of fail ure to learn, I think the supposed dangers of teaching practices to which students are not immedi ately receptive is greatly overrated--a point I tried to address in the present paper. My two sons dislike wind sprints in basketball practice, but such activities do seem to get them ready for play and neither one of them have talked about quitting basketball. As an educational psychologist I would argue that people frequently learn valuable lessons under adverse circumstances. They may strongly dislike the experience that taught them, but knowledge or skill acquired became valuable and attractive because of its functionality under other circumstances. For exampl e, many people hate English composition classes but later learn to love writing. In truth, structured and result-oriented teaching methods are not inherently unpleasant. For example, Direct Instruction (Engelmann, Becker, Car nine, et al) entails drill, recitation, and choral responding--all practices that are anathema to many educators. Kids, however, seem to love it. (8) When Stone says "Led by Dewey...the mainstream teaching profession has held that such 'intrinsic' or naturally occurring intere st will express itself provided that the student is confronted with a sufficiently meaningfu l or relevant or lifelike problem" Stone seems to think that this precludes all sorts of what he refers to as "purposeful actions of teachers and parents". I must not have made myself clear on this point. I n my view, Dewey does not restrict all purposeful actions of teachers and parents, rather he limits their options to approaches that would pique a youngster's interest. My reading of Dewey i s that his great break with educational tradition of his day was his insistence that true l earning had to be motivated by the genuine interest of the student, not by the insistence of a teacher/taskmaster. For example, Dewey would have opposed a teacher insisting that an unengaged student complete an assignment before going to recess. In fact, Dewey would have objected to th e idea of the teacher making an assignment purely on the basis of the teacher's assessment of the student's educational needs.

PAGE 64

5 of 5 I realize my responses are not as complete and as nuanced as your contentions deserve, but for the time being this is the best I can do. Again I appreciate your thoughtful response because I believe this issue may be at the heart of whether p ublic schools as we know them survive.

PAGE 65

1 of 3 Contributed Commentary on Volume 4 Number 8: Stone Developmentalism: An Obscure but Pervasive Restrict ion on Educational Improvement 27 April 1996Les McLeanlmclean@OISE.ON.CA Thanks to Rick Garlikov for taking the time to res pond to John Stone's "Developmentalism" article. Among the good qualitie s of Rick's response is that it is an illustration of how to follow the Edpolicy Guidelin es! I hope all who took the time to read Stone's article will also take the time to read Ric k's response (the response is only about one-quarter as long!). My purpose in this post is t o branch off from both of them to follow the question, "In any given situation, just WHAT is bei ng taught?" In the direct instruction lessons I have observed, myself or via videotape, I was convi nced that the overriding outcome, the one that would last (if anything did) was, "Do what the teacher says, believe what the teacher believes; don't think too much because it will slow you down." YES--I know that is not what most instructors inte nd. I know that is not all that happens. But I have been convinced by the tasks and the meth ods that it is mainly what happens. Rick's example of Saxon math and the follow-up questions i llustrates my point. No teacher can take the questions seriously and keep to the essence of dire ct instruction; nor should they, any more than whole language teachers should avoid word/sound cor respondences. My question, "What is taught?", however, came from Rick's "statistics" ex ample. I put in the quotation marks because I argue that Rick's 100-box problem does not teach st atistics in any meaningful sense of the term. I will argue that it teaches, "None of the most impor tant and difficult problems in life are statistical, but sometimes you can use statistics t o understand them better, maybe even solve them". Here is the task, as set out in Rick's respo nse to Stone: "Likewise, here is a statistics question that migh t work better to help teach statistics. I have been trying to work out ways to get kids to se e that one must take into account not only probabilities, but the value of outcomes, when asse ssing choices. For example, should you play a game where you get to choose a box to open if there are 100 boxes to choose from, $1000 in each of 99 of the boxes, but a bomb that will be fatally detonated in one of the boxes? If kids say, "yes, because those are good odds", I lower the amount of money in each box, which does not change the odds, but which starts to make them reconsider, and get the point. My stats question derives from different variation s on this game: Is there any difference between having 100 kids who think this is a good ga me to play each choose a box (all at the same time, so that all the boxes are spoken for), a nd having 100 kids play the game separately? Why or why not?" (Rick goes on to explain...) "If t hey play simultaneously one kid will for sure get killed, which seems like it makes the game not a good game for any of them, since they will be guaranteed to lose a friend, if not their own li fe. But if they play individually (with different sets of boxes, replacing the chosen box each time), maybe no one will get killed, and maybe two or eight or 100 of them will be killed. Yet the gam e may still seem like a good risk to some kids

PAGE 66

2 of 3to play on this basis. IS THERE a statistical diffe rence between the two ways of playing the game? If so, what? And if not, why does it seem oka y to play it one way to a kid but not another way? This is the sort of thing I consider to be a p urposeful interventionist, proactive sort of teaching question, but one which is consistent with Dewey and which would perhaps lead to students learning about statistical analysis better Yes? No? It is not a "natural" question, but one which I think is of the sort that works "naturally" to get kids more interested and thinking about statistics issues and more readily receptive to lea rning them, however else they are taught." My point: Except for the first, simple situation ( one person choosing one box from 100), people I know (from 'kids' to graduate students), c annot or will not learn enough probability to arrive at the correct odds themselves. Even if they arrive at an intuitive acceptance of the odds as stated by the teacher, the crucial question remains "How do you put a value on human life?" Even as a class exercise, this belongs in Decision Theory, and here again, "kids" and graduate students I know will not gain more than an exceptio nally superficial feeling for the "statistics". If the teacher can engage their interest, however, the y WILL see how crucial the value question is and how, IF they can answer that question THEN they can apply some simple statistics to arrive at an answer. My prediction is that most people wil l decide that they should not play the game at all, any more than they would play Russian roulette If you really want to teach statistics, there are, IMHO, better examples, e.g., error estimates i n opinion polling, bias resulting from non-random sampling in comparative studies. Here is an example from the National Pilot Mathema tics Test, elementary school, in the U.K., 1992. (The 'sign' was presented in a box so i t looked like a sign. Use of a calculator was allowed. 'lift' = 'elevator') -------------------------------------------------------------------This is the sign in a lift at an office block: This lift can carry up to 14 people In the morning rush, 269 people want to go up in th is lift.How many times must it go up? -------------------------------------------------------------------The expected answer is 20, but notice how many ass umptions are required for this to be correct (always full when people waiting, no one ta kes the stairs, no large parcels...). The best approach is to assume maximum simplicity, divide 26 9 by 14 and round up, still not an easy question for young people. But what is being assess ed? What is being taught? The example appeared in the article by Patricia Murphy (1995), "Sources of inequity: understanding students' responses to assessment" (Assessment in Education, 2(3), 249270), where she presents evidence that girls pay more attention to context t han boys and hence take more time with this task, maybe get it wrong, maybe omit it. Mathematic s tests are full of such examples, and the successful student has to learn to ignore most of t he contextual information and get directly to the simple calculations. Few would argue that mathemati cs teachers should be teaching this. Just one more example of an item that might be authentic in some circumstances but not desirable in any:Billy steals Joe's skateboard. As Billy skates away at 15 mph, Joe loads his 357 Magnum. If it takes Joe 20 seconds to load his Magnum, how far away will Billy be when he gets whacked?

PAGE 67

3 of 3 Best to end with another quotation from Rick's res ponse: "I think teachers need to be able to recognize and create teachable moments and then know what to do with them when they have them." Right on, Rick.

PAGE 68

1 of 6 Contributed Commentary on Volume 4 Number 8: Stone Developmentalism: An Obscure but Pervasive Restrict ion on Educational Improvement 26 April 1996Rick GarlikovDEMS042@UABDPO.DPO.UAB.EDU While I believe Prof. Stone's analysis correctly c haracterizes and chastises the views and (often mistaken) pedagogical philosophical understa nding of some teachers and school districts with which I am familiar, I think it (1) does not s ufficiently explain or take into account the rationales, and philosophical points, of other peop le for some of the approaches he refers to as "developmental", (2) does not fully appreciate some of the objections to experimentally demonstrated teaching methods, and (3) relies in cr ucial places on an ambiguity or vagueness in what it means for a teaching/learning method to be "natural" --a concept he argues is central to "developmentalist" philosophy. While that concept m ay be central, it seems to me that his objection to its involvement in pedagogical philoso phy depends effectively only on one sense of what it means to learn something "naturally", and n ot on a different, more important sense. While I do appreciate Prof. Stone's distinction between educationally appropriate" instruction and "developmentally appropriate" instruction, I think more needs to be said about what that means. I also believe that his paper makes some extremely im portant points and is substantially correct about the way many teachers and administrators conc eive of what they are doing. This response is meant more as a supplement than an attack. My ch ief concern in writing this is that the good aspects of some of the approaches Prof. Stone consi ders "developmental" not be thrown out with those elements he effectively argues are bad. First, as I have written repeatedly on AERA-C and EDPOLYAN, *I* believe it is wrong not to teach students in some way far more actively than just letting them discover things on their own as they happen to come to them. Pat Clifford us ed an expression I liked when she asks of teachers who let students work things out on their own whether they are doing anything "other than hosting the event". As I have put it, it would likely take students collectively 5000 years if they had to discover on their own what civilization has discovered collectively in the last 5000 years. Surely the point of "teaching" is to somehow more efficiently pass on to others the learning that is otherwise painfully slow to come about. The issue is what the most effective, and best, means of doing that is -where what is "best" may involve elements other than mere effectiveness. So none of what I write below is mea nt in any way to imply or say that I think children should not be actively taught things they may not come to on their own. And while I believe it is helpful for students to be ready to l earn what you are teaching, I believe an important element of teaching is purposefully "making" or get ting them ready. Second, I did not come to my ideas about education by training in education schools, so none of the (methods) books Prof. Stone mentions as being potentially influencing had any effect on me DIRECTLY. The possible exception is Dewey, so me of which I have read; but I read Dewey after most of my educational ideas were alrea dy formed, and tended to either agree or

PAGE 69

2 of 6disagree rather than, I think, simply being influen ced or inculcated. As Prof. Stone says, however, there is no way to tell how much indirect influence Dewey or others before me may have had on my thinking. Third, MY criticism of schools is not "their conti nuing failure to equip students with the academic and workplace skills needed in an era of i ncreasing economic competition." My personal view is that there are far more efficient ways of doing this than school, and that the purpose of school is to give students a broader ran ge of knowledge and skills than whatever the workplace may likely demand, so that they can do we ll in life as well as work, and so that they themselves can bring about important changes in soc iety and the workplace rather than just being able to adjust to those changes. Plus, I take the v iew that learning things is a great thing, often just because they are interesting to learn -wheth er they have any known application at the time or not. Too much of great importance has been disco vered just because people followed "idle" curiosity or interests instead of spending their ti me learning what was already known to be useful, to make school just be a place where inform ation that is known to be applicable at the work place is taught. In those places where schools do not teach well en ough to adequately prepare students for the workplace, that signifies a problem on my view only because that should be a minimal outcome of the sort of education I seek for student s. But the problem may not be solely that of the schools' in those cases, or at least not of the teachers in those schools. It may be a larger social problem, even in affluent suburban school di stricts. Prof. Stone says that developmentalism is a "doctr ine that pervades teacher education and one that disposes the teaching profession to favor certain practices and to ignore others regardless of empirically demonstrated merit." My understandin g from reading, discussion, and from personal experience is that teachers (like anyone e lse) are disposed to favor specific practices with which they are familiar and comfortable -fre quently teaching as they have been taught, rather than teaching as they have been taught to te ach in ed schools -and that any practice which differs from what they are comfortable with is diff icult to get them to accept on the basis of ANY kind of theory, whether overt or underlying. I have even found that you can demonstrate a method to teachers which is consistent with any phi losophy of education they may have and still NOT get them to adopt that method in their own teac hing. I did one lesson with a third grade classroom one time that worked out so much better t han any teachers thought possible (and even better than I thought likely) that the teacher's mo uth literally dropped open as kids were answering questions and making inferences that all the teachers and administrators had said was impossible for them to do. Yet the teacher's unders tanding of what had happened was not about the method, but about how good *I* was. NOTHING I c ould do or say convinced her she could do the same thing using the method. Further, it took many of the theories, such as who le-language, a lot of "promotion and selling" to win acceptance at all; so I am not quit e ready to accept that teachers have some underlying disposition to accept the approaches Pro f. Stone refers to as developmentalist (in what might be facetiously referred to some sort of consp iracy theory of developmentalism in education). I think salesmanship, whether based on merit or not, is perhaps more important than (underlying) philosophy or demonstrated effectivene ss. With regard to (1) above --there being grounds bes ides "natural development" for advocating methods other than those research has sh own effective: I am familiar with the rationales of some math con structivists and some whole language advocates. I have read Constance Kamii (who worked with Piaget) and frequently discussed her writing with her, and I have read some of the Goodm an's works on whole-language. Their claims are that just knowing algorithms in the case of mat h, and just being able to PRONOUNCE words out loud is not the same thing as understanding or doing math, or as reading. They are not making claims about what is natural, but about the ultimate ineffectiveness of certain kinds of

PAGE 70

3 of 6direct instruction that have SEEMED to work, but wh ich they argue have failed, or at least failed large numbers of students. I won't go into the vali dity of their evidence here, but the point is their argument is quite different from anything about wha t is natural. Now Dr. Kamii in some cases does seem to make the further claim that children CANNOT learn certain things before certain ages; bu t at other times she backs off from that and says that the direct methods often used in schools DO NOT teach children, even though children can be trained to perform certain tasks that make t hem look like they are doing math. She and I differ quite frequently about what children have le arned and what they understand, and how to tell. But that is a very different matter from her having some sort of disposition toward what is "natural". And we both agree that direct methods of teaching math traditionally do not help kids understand it, though we have different evidence fo r that conclusion. As to reading, even the "Hooked on Phonics" adds s howing kids pronouncing big words makes it fairly clear that they are not reading wit h any comprehension. And many elementary school teachers can point to cases where students c an pronounce even familiar words from a page of print without having any understanding of what t hey mean in the context of "decoding them from print". I have constructed such a phonetic exa mple for adults, where the person reading it out loud does not know what he is reading, but anyo ne listening to him will understand it perfectly. Further, although SOME practitioners thi nk teaching via whole language means they are not supposed to teach any sound-symbol correspo ndence, the whole language approach as I have read about it and heard it advocated, DOES esp ouse the teaching of soundsymbol correspondence as necessary but not sufficient for teaching reading. But moreover, even teaching sound-symbol correspondence is done in a way differ ent from mere drill. There is a difference between practice and drill in teaching anything, an d I will get to that in a moment. The references to "natural learning" that I have s een in Whole Language tracts have been merely to point out that it is possible to learn to read without certain kinds of drill and "instruction" just as we learn to talk without dril l and "instruction" (other than the kinds of things parents do sort of "naturally" in "teaching" kids t o talk or teaching them particular words). I don't remember reading anything that argued teaching read ing in this way was better because it was natural, just that it was possible. The "better" ha d to do with other sorts of claims. (2) Objections to experimentally demonstrated teac hing methods: Prof. Stone says "The object of experimental research is to demonstrate t he impact of an independent variable as an agent of change." This gives rise to two different kinds of problems for a practitioner, one of which Stone thinks is irrelevant, but which I want to try to give more force. The first problem is that there is much published which seems quite clea rly to be flawed research, or interpretations of research, in that it does not isolate an independen t variable and show its effect. Recently on AERA-C Barak Rosenshine, himself, raised the issue of why the evidence for direct instruction, etc. was ignored by so many people. He pointed to r esearch and claims about the Saxon direct instruction teaching in math. As the discussion pro gressed, someone posted a sample lesson from a Saxon math textbook. The lesson included a number of questions after the text or explanatory part. It seemed quite clear to me that the nature o f the questions was extremely important for fostering understanding and for any application oth er than mere memory in closely similar circumstances. (And my argument is that you can onl y memorize so much math; and if that is the way you learn it, you will be much more limited in your math ability than if you understand it AND can do much automatically from practice.) I tol d Barak that I would be very surprised if Saxon math books WITHOUT the questions could yield anywhere near the same test results the Saxon math books as they are WITH the questions did But THAT experiment has not been done. The point is that "direct instruction" is not an isolated independent variable in whatever studies were done on the Saxon method. So that even if the Saxon method is a good method for teaching math (which it seems to be, according to B arak), that does not show "direct instruction" is what is the key element for math instruction or for the Saxon method. The problem in general

PAGE 71

4 of 6is that in any complex situation such as a classroo m, it is very difficult to isolate variables and test them with controls, even if one does this thro ugh various meta-analyses simply statistically. Second, I assume Prof. Stone would not advocate us e of drugs or electric shock therapy if these were shown by research to drastically increas e learning. What is sought in schools is effective teaching that is also not Draconian in so me way. The argument against some forms of drill (and drill alone) is that it IS Draconian, no t physically as drugs or electrical shock would be, but in other important ways, primarily in its killi ng all interest in the subject so that whatever is gained in the short run by making kids drill is los t in the long run by their never wanting to take any more math, or read any more books, than they ha ve to in order to get a grade. It is not that drill is conceived of as bad because it is unnatura l, but that it is conceived of as bad because it is ultimately counterproductive to learning though it may help kids who work in stores count change back better. I would argue that drill in things which are unimp ortant (e.g., learning state capitals in alphabetical order of states) is bad because it tak es time away from learning more useful things (even if they also are memorized) and because it ma kes kids lose interest in school, since it is a place where "stupid stuff", or stuff to be done in stupid ways, is arbitrarily assigned for no good reason. Further, as I said, drill is different from practice; and there are lots of ways to give practice without doing mere drill. For example play ing "21" or Blackjack gives plenty of crucial adding/subtracting practice. Playing team "War" wit h cards, where pairs of opponents turn over pairs of cards, and the higher pair sum wins the op ponent's cards, gives addition practice. *IF* you can make the practice fun, is that not be tter than making drill tedious --if you achieve the same learning. Not better because it is more effective in the short run, but because it may be more effective in the long run for students' schooling in general, and is more humane. I am not against memorization, nor am I against drill The argument is over the specifics and the outcomes with regard to a reasonable span of time. If you teach kids to read, but make them hate to read, what of value have you accomplished? If yo u teach kids lower level math skills in such a way that they hit the wall in algebra, what of valu e have you accomplished? Research that is important is research that will take into account t hese longer term issues, not just tell which methods help 3rd graders add or subtract the fastes t and most accurately. This is not an issue about "development"; it is an issue about what give s the best results, where results are not narrowly construed. Now there will be disagreement about WHICH things need to be learned automatically, but that is a different issue. E.g., Bernice Wolfso n and I used to argue about the point of teaching multiplication tables. I say it is crucial so that you can have more chance at recognizing potential common denominators when working with fractions, an d more chance at solving algebra problems that require factoring, etc. If you cannot readily see these things, you may not even think of the right method for solving a problem, le t alone not be able to do the actual calculations very well. She had her own ways of doing multiplica tion and had never learned the multiplication tables. But she did not go on to higher level math, and she admittedly took forever to multiply in her head or on paper. She thought that was sufficie nt; I thought it deficient, and that she had perhaps missed a lot of neat stuff because of her i nability to automatically recognize combinations involving multiples. (3) What "natural" teaching methods are: There is an ambiguity here that is important. In t he medical example Stone gives ("The artificial creation of immunities through the use o f 'unnatural' and invasive vaccination is an historic example."), such vaccines are only unnatur al in that they may not occur in nature (in the amounts needed for vaccinating everyone -since co wpox virus did exist in nature), but they work by using the body's quite natural response to invasive molecules. So, although polio vaccine is "unnatural", the way it works is not. When Stone says "Led by Dewey...the mainstream tea ching profession has held that such

PAGE 72

5 of 6'intrinsic' or naturally occurring interest will ex press itself provided that the student is confronte d with a sufficiently meaningful or relevant or lifel ike problem" Stone seems to think that this precludes all sorts of what he refers to as "purpos eful actions of teachers and parents". I don't see this. I don't see that if I get kids to play "21" t hat is somehow different in terms of purposeful action on my part from trying to make them do works heets for a grade. One might even make a game out of the worksheets. The point is not whethe r the teacher is doing anything invasive or unnatural or purposeful, but whether whatever the t eacher is doing is more likely to induce learning. If you can INDUCE learning to occur natur ally, that is quite different from waiting for learning to occur naturally. Now, SOME teachers do nothing (but "host the event ") when they teach, but surely that is not what Dewey meant for teachers to do. Am I being less instructive or less purposeful or more "natural" when I tell a kid "if you play in the str eet and get hit by a car, it will squash you in the same way you squash a bug with your shoe; and you w ill be just as dead as the bug" and the kid UNDERSTANDS that, than if I say "I'll spank you if you go near the street to play." I say the former may be much more effective with some kids at some times; and it is not less purposeful or more intervening than the latter. And it is consist ent with what Dewey was describing. Likewise, here is a statistics question that might work bette r to help teach statistics. I have been trying to work out ways to get kids to see that one must take into account not only probabilities, but the value of outcomes, when assessing choices. For exam ple, should you play a game where you get to choose a box to open if there are 100 boxes to c hoose from, $1000 in each of 99 of the boxes, but a bomb that will be fatally detonated in one of the boxes? If kids say, "yes because those are good odds", I lower the amount of money in each box which does not change the odds, but which starts to make them reconsider, and get the p oint. My stats question derives from different variations on this game: Is there any difference be tween having 100 kids who think this is a good game to play each choose a box (all at the same tim e, so that all the boxes are spoken for), and having 100 kids play the game separately? Why or wh y not? If they play simultaneously one kid will for sure get killed, which seems like it makes the game not a good game for any of them, since they will be guaranteed to lose a friend, if not their own life. But if they play individually (with different sets of boxes, replacing the chosen box each time), maybe no one will get killed, and maybe two or eight or 100 of them will be kille d. Yet the game may still seem like a good risk to some kids to play on this basis. IS THERE a statistical difference between the two ways of playing the game? If so, what? And if not, why does it seem okay to play it one way to a kid but not another way? This is the sort of thing I consid er to be a purposeful interventionist, proactive sort of teaching question, but one which is consist ent with Dewey and which would perhaps lead to students learning about statistical analysis bet ter. Yes? No? It is not a "natural" question, but one which I think is of the sort that works "natura lly" to get kids more interested and thinking about statistics issues and more readily receptive to learning them, however else they are taught. The notion of what is natural, developmentally app ropriate, interventionist, or "constructivist" is not clear. I have presented NCT M with a socratic method that I say gets kids to understand "place-value" in math, and they say it i s nothing but a prescription for teaching; and they reject it. I say it takes thought and skill an d art and understanding to use the method properly; they say it doesn't. I say it shows kids understand placevalue; they say kids only give the answers I am prompting. I say those answers can 't be prompted without the kids' understanding. The point is that there is no clear cut distinctio n between what is natural and what is purposeful intervention in the way that either cons tructivists or Stone seem to think. And sometimes it is not clear what is intrinsic or extr insic. If my students just don't like me, than they may not respond interestedly to my above stat probl em; if they do, they may. There is an element of the extrinsic in making something interesting pe rhaps. Isn't the real issue trying to avoid the Draconian or the harmful, and also finding what is

PAGE 73

6 of 6most effective in a way that does not have some kin d of harmful "side-effects"? What is the point of trying to argue whether a method is teacher dire cted or not? Surely that is irrelevant. But on the other hand, my experience indicates to me that if you can get students to see the point of a procedure or exercise, or if you can make it intere sting in some way (or not kill interest in it), then whatever other sort of instruction you need to use to help or get them to learn it, will work better. I just don't see any of this as an either/o r sort of thing for most subjects. In quoting Armstrong, Stone says with disapproval that "many teachers have come to believe teaching is more art than science". There a re important "art" aspects to teaching. One of these is figuring out what kids already know that m ight help them learn new concepts better. One of these is figuring out what kids do know or just seem to know, or don't know/understand at all AFTER you have "taught" them. There is, after all, an art to communication in general. And one of the art aspects of education is figuring out wha t you need to try to get the significance of what you are teaching through to students. And one is be ing able to make something interesting to students. I write all this because I can't imagine that mere drill and mere lecturing and merely holding the threat of a grade over a kid's head (or promising a reward) is the best way to teach much even though it makes some short term gains in some cases; but on the other hand, I think what Prof. Stone writes is true about too many teac hers. And, like him, I don't think merely being there to try to wait for readiness or that right te achable moment is the best way to teach anyone anything. I think teachers need to be able to recog nize and create teachable moments and then know what to do with them when they have them. One pet peeve: the holding of Benjamin Spock respo nsible for the permissive society. What Spock advocated in Baby and Child Care was that babies did not need to be on a rigid feeding schedule whereby they were given a certain amount of formula every four hours even when not hungry and denied food when they displayed signs of hunger just because it happened to be three hours or three hours and a half. Spock recommended firm discipline where it was needed, but did not think (as I do not) that discip line for the mere sake of rigidity or arbitrary or average scheduling was warranted. Surely recommendi ng more flexible feeding times has not undone our society. Finally, I believe it is not age development that generally creates readiness, but development through meaningful exposure or experien ce. I suspect that if you can expose kids to things earlier in ways that are meaningful to them, you can teach kids a lot more than most people suspect without "pressuring" them, and witho ut thereby being "unnatural" in the sense of cramming it down their throats.


xml version 1.0 encoding UTF-8 standalone no
mods:mods xmlns:mods http:www.loc.govmodsv3 xmlns:xsi http:www.w3.org2001XMLSchema-instance xsi:schemaLocation http:www.loc.govmodsv3mods-3-1.xsd
mods:relatedItem type host
mods:identifier issn 1068-2341mods:part
mods:detail volume mods:number 4issue 8series Year mods:caption 19961996Month April4Day 2121mods:originInfo mods:dateIssued iso8601 1996-04-21