USF Libraries
USF Digital Collections

From just war to just peace

MISSING IMAGE

Material Information

Title:
From just war to just peace re-visioning just war theory from a feminist perspective
Physical Description:
Book
Language:
English
Creator:
Malone, Naomi
Publisher:
University of South Florida
Place of Publication:
Tampa, Fla.
Publication Date:

Subjects

Subjects / Keywords:
peace
morality
ethics
feminism
war
Dissertations, Academic -- Political Science -- Masters -- USF   ( lcsh )
Genre:
government publication (state, provincial, terriorial, dependent)   ( marcgt )
bibliography   ( marcgt )
theses   ( marcgt )
non-fiction   ( marcgt )

Notes

Summary:
ABSTRACT: This paper studies the history of just war theory and critiques it from various feminist perspectives. Using a definition of war as inseparable from the system within which it is embedded, the paper contends that just war theory has been incorporated into the realist paradigm that predominates current political thought, making it susceptible to manipulation. Most importantly, this usurpation has shifted just war theory's focus from jus ad bellum to jus in bello considerations, seriously weakening its deterrent effects on war. The paper proposes its replacement with a just peace theory, discussing several existing frameworks and explaining the important part women are playing to achieve its principles. It concludes that although just war principles might still be helpful as a framework for limiting the worst excesses of war, current applications do not adequately meet the presumption against war and for peaceful settlement of disputes that the theory's originators envisioned. Just peace theory is an active theory that promotes practices leading to the reduction of violence in all arenas and at all levels, from fights in the schoolyard to ethnic conflicts and beyond, offering concrete examples that can strengthen the last resort criteria of just war theory.
Thesis:
Thesis (M.A.)--University of South Florida, 2004.
Bibliography:
Includes bibliographical references.
System Details:
System requirements: World Wide Web browser and PDF reader.
System Details:
Mode of access: World Wide Web.
Statement of Responsibility:
by Naomi Malone.
General Note:
Title from PDF of title page.
General Note:
Document formatted into pages; contains 62 pages.

Record Information

Source Institution:
University of South Florida Library
Holding Location:
University of South Florida
Rights Management:
All applicable rights reserved by the source institution and holding location.
Resource Identifier:
aleph - 001469438
oclc - 55732456
notis - AJR1192
usfldc doi - E14-SFE0000339
usfldc handle - e14.339
System ID:
SFS0025034:00001


This item is only available as the following downloads:


Full Text
xml version 1.0 encoding UTF-8 standalone no
record xmlns http:www.loc.govMARC21slim xmlns:xsi http:www.w3.org2001XMLSchema-instance xsi:schemaLocation http:www.loc.govstandardsmarcxmlschemaMARC21slim.xsd
leader nam Ka
controlfield tag 001 001469438
003 fts
006 m||||e|||d||||||||
007 cr mnu|||uuuuu
008 040524s2004 flu sbm s000|0 eng d
datafield ind1 8 ind2 024
subfield code a E14-SFE0000339
035
(OCoLC)55732456
9
AJR1192
b SE
SFE0000339
040
FHM
c FHM
090
JA66
1 100
Malone, Naomi.
0 245
From just war to just peace
h [electronic resource] :
re-visioning just war theory from a feminist perspective /
by Naomi Malone.
260
[Tampa, Fla.] :
University of South Florida,
2004.
502
Thesis (M.A.)--University of South Florida, 2004.
504
Includes bibliographical references.
516
Text (Electronic thesis) in PDF format.
538
System requirements: World Wide Web browser and PDF reader.
Mode of access: World Wide Web.
500
Title from PDF of title page.
Document formatted into pages; contains 62 pages.
520
ABSTRACT: This paper studies the history of just war theory and critiques it from various feminist perspectives. Using a definition of war as inseparable from the system within which it is embedded, the paper contends that just war theory has been incorporated into the realist paradigm that predominates current political thought, making it susceptible to manipulation. Most importantly, this usurpation has shifted just war theory's focus from jus ad bellum to jus in bello considerations, seriously weakening its deterrent effects on war. The paper proposes its replacement with a just peace theory, discussing several existing frameworks and explaining the important part women are playing to achieve its principles. It concludes that although just war principles might still be helpful as a framework for limiting the worst excesses of war, current applications do not adequately meet the presumption against war and for peaceful settlement of disputes that the theory's originators envisioned. Just peace theory is an active theory that promotes practices leading to the reduction of violence in all arenas and at all levels, from fights in the schoolyard to ethnic conflicts and beyond, offering concrete examples that can strengthen the last resort criteria of just war theory.
590
Adviser: Susan Stoudinger Northcutt
653
peace.
morality.
ethics.
feminism.
war.
690
Dissertations, Academic
z USF
x Political Science
Masters.
773
t USF Electronic Theses and Dissertations.
4 856
u http://digital.lib.usf.edu/?e14.339



PAGE 1

From Just War To Just Peace: Re -Visioning Just War Theory From A Feminist Perspective by Naomi Malone A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts Department of Political Science College of Arts and Sciences University of South Florida Major Professor: Susan Stoudinger Northcutt, Ph.D. Member: Carolyn DiPalma, Ph.D. Member: Michael Gibbons, Ph.D. Date of Approval: March 31, 2004 Keywords: war, feminism, ethics, morality, peace Copyright 2004, Naomi Malone

PAGE 2

i Table of Contents List of Tables ii Abstract iii Chapter One: Introduction 1 Chapter Two: The History of Just War Theory Greek and Roman Sources 10 Christian Reflections on Just War 14 Secular Revisions 16 Just War in the Twentieth Century 18 Chapter Three: Feminist Analysis of Just War Introduction 25 Feminist Ethics 25 Feminist Critiques of Just War 32 Conclusion 38 Chapter Four: Just Peace 41 Chapter Five: Conclusion 48 References 50 Appendix A: Just Peacemaking: Ten Practices for Abolishing War 54

PAGE 3

ii List of Tables Table 1 Just War Criteria 19 Table 2 Just War Criteria (addition) 23

PAGE 4

iii From Just War To Just Peace: Re-V isioning Just War Theory From A Feminist Perspective Naomi Malone ABSTRACT This paper studies the history of just war theory and critiques it from various feminist perspectives. Using a def inition of war as inseparable from the system within which it is embedded, the paper contends t hat just war theory has been incorporated into the realist paradigm that predominates current political thought, making it susceptible to manipulatio n. Most importantly, this usurpation has shifted just war theory’s focus from jus ad bellum to jus in bello considerations, seriously weakening it s deterrent effects on war. The paper proposes its replacement with a just peac e theory, discussing several existing frameworks and explaining the important part women are playing to achieve its principles. It concludes that although just war principles might still be helpful as a framework for limiting the worst excesse s of war, current applications do not adequately meet the presumpt ion against war and for peaceful settlement of disputes that the theory’s originators envisioned. Just peace theory is an active theory that promotes practi ces leading to the reduction of violence in all arenas and at all levels, from fights in the schoolyard to ethnic conflicts and beyond, offering concrete examples that can strengt hen the last resort criteria of just war theory.

PAGE 5

1 Introduction But the real and lasting victories ar e those of peace, and not of war. -Ralph Waldo Emerson, Worship Traditional just war doctrine is enjoying a revival of interest in the wake of transforming global interrelationships and drastic improvements in military technology. In spite of optimism in some quarters that globalization and the expansion of liberal democracy is the ans wer for world peace, events such as the genocide in Rwanda, the attacks on the World Trade Center, as well as longstanding conflicts such as the Isr aeli-Palestinian conflict and the simmering Indian-Pakistani standoff over Kashmir indica te that there are deeper issues at work when it comes to war and peace. The increasing disparity between rich and poor nations; ethnic, cultural and religio us tensions; and nuclear proliferation are just some of the many issues that ensure that war and violence will continue to play a predominant role in internati onal relations within the near future. What is the definition of war? The Bl ackwell Dictionary of Political Science defines war as “armed conflict between or ganized groups with objectives they deem to be irreconcilable.” This paper us es Joshua Goldstein’s definition of war as “lethal intergroup violence” and the war system within which wars exist as: “the interrelated way that societies organize themselves to participate in potential and actual wars. In this perspective, war is less a series of events than a system with continuity through time. This system includes, for example, military spending

PAGE 6

2 and attitudes about war, in addition to standing military forces and actual fighting.”1 There are three main strands of we stern philosophical thought about war: pacifism, realism and just war theory. No t all pacifists necessarily disagree with the use of just war theory as a basis for evaluating the necessity for war, but they believe that the only conclusion that c an be made from this analysis is that the war cannot be justified and that all conf licts can be resolved through arbitration rather than violence. Realists, on t he other hand, are prof oundly skeptical of using moral precepts in any foreign policy issues, war included. Its proponents argue that power and nationa l security are the only motivating factors in interstate relations and thus prompt any de cisions regarding war. In contrast to both of these viewpoints, just war theory attempts to re strict wars between states by subjecting those in authority to certain precepts concerning their commencement, conduct and termination. The value of just war theory lies in its ability not to describe the world as it is, but to provide a framework for debating the justice of particular wars. Thus, theorists and leaders have shaped and supple mented its principles to adapt to the requirements of their particular so cieties and times. The first chapter concentrates on the historical literature of just war theory, sho wing that just war theory is written exclusiv ely by and for men. 1 Goldstein, Joshua. How Gender Shapes the War System and Vice Versa. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 2001. War and Gender. Joshua Goldstein. 16 March 2003

PAGE 7

3 Its secular beginnings in ancient Rome and Greece influenced the early Christian apologist Saint Augustine to re concile Christian pacifism with Rome’s need to defend its borders against encroachi ng invaders. Later, as the Roman Empire splintered into factions that progr essively coalesced into states, theorists supplemented or reinterpret ed its doctrines to justify wars between themselves. Gradually, the theory returned to its secu lar roots as the Enlightenment eroded the invincibility of the Church, event ually becoming embedded in international laws of war originally designed by the Dutch jurist Grotius and Christian scholastics such as Francisco Suarez and Francisco Vitoria. Finally, a European system of states based upon the principles of state sovereignty and international law arose from the ashes of the Thirty Years War and culminated in the “Peace of Westphalia.”. During the 19th and early 20th centuries, this combination of the codification of war with the ascendancy of state sovereignty led to a significant shift of the doctrine’s em phasis from the original jus ad bellum (just cause) questions to those of jus in bello (just methods during war), allowing the theory to flourish even as Western nations use se lf-interested reasons to justify their positions. This overlying theme conti nues to emphasize “balance –of–power” as the world shaping principle, subjugating ju st war theory to the role of apologist. As Nicholas Rengger indicates “many of the arguments surrounding deterrence policy during the Cold War, military inte rventions (or lack of them) from the 1960’s to the 1990’s and the “war against terrorism” now are couched in the language that would be broadly familiar to those theologians, philosophers and

PAGE 8

4 jurists who largely created the just wa r tradition, even if the context of the debates has changed beyond recognition.”2 Modern secular literature purporting to represent non-realist views includes Michael Walzer’s wor ks, among them his influential Just and Unjust Wars and Brian Orend’s book which stresses not only the two dimensions usually described as just war theory ( jus ad bellum and jus in bello ) but the equally important principle of jus post bellum (just end to war.) These works accentuate a legalistic paradigm based on universal human rights. In contra st, there is still a strong religious strand of just war t hought that continues to emphasize the original casuistical tradition, especially found in the American Catholic Bishops’ The Challenge of Peace The references cited in Brian Orend’s recent book War and International Justice: A Kantian Perspective include only two books that include feminist viewpoints on the topic, both edited by Jean Bethke Elshtain. This paucity reflects both the current “ma leness” of the topic and the lack of feminist writers who either have addressed the issue or have been allowed to publish their thoughts in mainstream journals. Accordi ng to Goldstein, this exclusion mirrors the inherent inhospitability of the fields of political science and international relations to issues about women and gender. He contends that feminist works written about war and peace are written primarily by women and that these feminist contributions are seldom found in mainstream journals. 2 Rengger, Nicholas. “On The Just War Tradition In The Twenty-First Century.” International Affairs 78.2 (2002): 353.

PAGE 9

5 Within this feminist literature, Jean Bethke Elshtain’s works on just war theory continue to create a postmodern as well as religious space within the larger just war debate. Sara Ruddick and Carol Cohn are some other feminists who specifically address just war theory. There is also a body of feminist wo rk on war and peace that sheds light on many other feminist perspectives on war and violence: “From Lourdes Baneria's and Rebecca Blank's (1989) feminist em piricist discussion of "Women and the Economics of Military Spending" to Elshta in's (1987) postmodernist explorations of gendered war narratives; from Judith St iehm's (1989) empirical research on women in the U.S. militar y to the epistemologically varied essays that form Adrienne Harris' and Ynestra King's (1989) volume on how feminists think about peace and the parallel volume edited by Sharon MacDonald, Pat Holden, and Shirley Ardener (1988) on images of wom en in war and peace, we find a stream of efforts to consider who owns, is c onstituted by, accepts, challenges, and rejects IR's wars and peaces.”3 According to Jacqui True, these represent “very contradictory and overlapping posit ions, discourses and practices.”4 Nonetheless, this diversity does not prec lude the possibility of a feminist debate on just war theory. Feminist ethics derives much of its vitality from such diversity. The chapter analyzes just war from these broad perspectives found in “the three epistemologies commonly referred to in the feminist IR literature as feminist 3 Christine Sylvester, “Feminist Theory and Gender Studies in International Relations”, International Studies Notes, 16/17, (Fall 1991/ Winter 1992) 3/1:32-38 Feminist Theory and Gender Studies. International Studies Association. 23 June, 2002. 4 True, Jacqui, “Feminism”, Theories of Internatio nal Relations, eds. S. Burchill and A. Linklater, New York: St. Martin’s Press, 1995, 1996, 212.

PAGE 10

6 empiricism, feminist standpoin t and feminist postmodernism.”5 Feminist empiricists argue that the male-centric fr amework within which research is done in political science and in ternational relations make s value-free and objective knowledge impossible. Judith Stiehm’s em pirical research on women in the U.S. Military, Arms and the Enlisted Woman is representative of this viewpoint. Feminist standpoint theorists believe that people's perceptions of society differ because they have different outlooks. Borrowing from Marxism, feminist standpoint theorists contend that women have access to knowledge unavailable to mainstream society because of their ma rginalization. They attempt to take account of the standpoints of a diversity of women’s viewpoints, as well as those of other marginalized groups. According to Christine Sylvester, this viewpoint argues “that women's biology and-or habit ual social assignments as mothers and caretakers position women against the vi olence of war as a means of settling disputes (e.g. Brock-Utne, 1985; Rudd ick, 1989), and help them to develop a politically viable standpoint on wars, peaces insecurities, and militaristic tamings in our lives (Reardon, 1985; Enloe, 1983).”6 Feminist postmodernists, on the other hand, are skeptical about universa l categories such as “women” and “science”, seeking forms of knowledge and tr uth that show the fractured nature of identities, allowing them to discove r and resolve existing injustices.7 5 True, 213. 6 Sylvester. 7 These definitions are based on several different sources, primarily Tr ue, 214,215 and Sylvester, Christine. Feminist Theory and International Relations in a Postmodern Era. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994.10,11.

PAGE 11

7 There is a general consensus that wo men value peace more than men, and several statistical studies do point to t he fact that they are more actively involved in peace movements than men are.8 However, the issue runs much deeper than whether women are by nat ure more “peacable” than men: Virginia Sapiro and Pamela Conover’s analysis of American surveys (dealing with hypothetical security policies as well as concrete questions about the use of military force and its consequences) shows that “when we moved from the abstract to the concrete—from hypothet ical wars to the Gulf War—the distance separating women and men gr ew, and on every measure, women reacted more negatively.”9 Some feminists try to distance themselves from such studies by arguing that they only emphasize differences between masculine and feminine characteristics, sh ifting the focus away from the goal of incorporating women’s contributi ons into mainstream decision-making about war and peace. However, others call attention to the difference concluding that “feminist perspecti ves on peace, security, and conflict resolution challenge a traditional underst anding of peace processes as the expression and ratification of power over such as when one side forces the other to accept the terms of cease-fire, emphasizing instead an 8 Peach, Lucinda. “An Alternative to Pacifism? Feminism and Just-War Theory,” 1994. Bringing Peace Home.: Feminism, Violence and Nature. Eds. K.J. Warren and D.L. Cady. Bloomington and Indianapolis: Indiana Univ ersity Press, 1996. 193. 9 Eichenberg, R.C. “Gender Differences in Public Attitudes toward the Use of Force by the United States, 1990-2003”. International Security 28.1 (2003):110-41.

PAGE 12

8 understanding of peace as a process of negotiation and conflict resolution where both sides come out as winners.”10 This paper’s discussion of feminist ethics integrates these various discourses into an analysis and critique of just war that illuminates the gendered nature of war and the war system within which it is embedded, making the case that just war theory’s efficacy is current ly compromised by its containment within the realist paradigm. The next chapter proposes the theory of just peace, a holistic theoretical and practical framework based on the belief that war is not episodic but endemic within the fabric of our societies. Rather than repudiati ng the existing world system, this belief offers the hope that wars can be prevented from within by creating modes of negotiation and rec onciliation practices to reduce and eventually end the necessity for violence. This paper contends that just war theory’s usurpation by realism downplays the important princi ple of “last resort”, pl acing war over and above negotiation and conflict resolution as a viable method for securing peace. It acknowledges that just war theory can provide a structure for analyzing certain wars in very specific ways. Howeve r, an analysis solely within this framework cannot offer a comprehensive picture because it does not take into consideration the wider social and cultural aspects withi n which the war takes place. Also, its rhetoric is frequently co-opt ed to achieve political and so cial ends (both selfish 10 Rabrenovic, Gordana and Laura Roskos. “Introdu ction: Civil Society, Feminism, and the Gendered Politics of War and Peace.” National Women’s Studies Association Journal 13.2 (2001):43.

PAGE 13

9 and altruistic) that may not be just. In addition, there is a continued shift of emphasis from jus ad bellum to jus in bello principles, making it easier for governments to justify wars as long as they are perceived to be complying with international rules of law. For example: The United States and it allies prac tice a new style of legal warfarewhat Schmitt called “Bellum Americ anum”-that hinges on precision-guided bombs, standardized targeting, acc epted levels and types of collateral damage, and high bomber fli ght altitudes. Once considered obstacles to the war effort, military lawyers hav e been integrated into strategic and tactical decisions, and even accompany tr oops into battle. Never has the conduct of war been so legalistic.11 The paper concludes that although just war principles can serve as a framework for limiting the worst excesse s of war, current applications do not adequately meet the presum ption against war and peaceful settlement of disputes that the theory’s originators envisioned. On the other hand, far from being a mere synthesis of just war theor y and pacifism, just peace is an active theory that promotes practi ces leading to the reduction of violence in all arenas and at all levels, from fights in the schoolyard to ethnic conflicts and beyond. These practices offer just war theory c oncrete examples of actions that are available as “last resorts”, creating the po ssibility that just war theorists’ debates will again emphasize the principles us ed to decide whether a war should be fought rather than whether a war that has already begun is fought justly. 11 Rengger, 356.

PAGE 14

10 The History of Just War Theory Greek and Roman Sources An unjust peace is better than a just war. Marcus Tullius Cicero Thucydides’ history of the Peloponnesian War, particularly his description of the Melian Dialogue, suggests that the Greeks approached war from a realist perspective. In his narrative, the At henian delegates sent to secure Melian support in their war respond to the Me lian’s desire to remain neutral by proclaiming: “Our opinion of the gods and our knowledge of men lead us to conclude that it is a general and necessa ry law of nature to rule wherever one can. This is not a law that we made ourse lves, nor were we the first to act upon it when it was made. We f ound it already in existence, and we shall leave it to exist for ever among those who come a fter us. We are merely acting in accordance with it, and we know that y ou or anybody else with the same power as ours would be acting in precisely the same way.” 12 However, several Greek philosophers disagreed with that point of view, exclaiming that Athens did not fight unjus t wars. One of these was Isocrates, who in his correspondence with the Cypr iot prince Nicocles exhorted him to make no unjust wars, honor all treaties and refr ain from the desire to rule all men. Further, in direct contra st to the Athenian delegation’s reply to the Melians, 12 Thucydides’ The Peloponnesian War, Book 5, Chapter 7, translated by Rex Warner. London: Penguin, 1955. Quoted in Luard, Evan. Basic Te xts in International Relations. New York: St. Martin’s Press, 1992 120-126.

PAGE 15

11 Isocrates declared that the foreign policy of Athens followed the principle “It is not just for the strong to rule the weak.”13 Another dissenting voice was Demosthenes, who praised the justness of the Athenians (in the aftermath of their defeat in the Peloponnesian Wars) by arguing that Athens was defending all of the Greeks against Sparta.14 Of course, this rhetor ic did not include wars against the “barbarian” states outside of the Panhellenic ar ena, as noted by Doyne Dawson: “Since there was consi dered little possibility of a reasonable communication with foreigners, the only way to settle disputes with them was by battle. And the only norm in such battle was what benefited the city-state and its needs. All particular actions or general prac tices in battle were judged solely by how expedient they were toward military and thus civic success.”15 This ability to separate the Gr eeks from the “others/barbarians” allowed them to make a di stinction between the moralit y of wars fought amongst themselves and those fought with “barbarians”. For example, Plato in his Republic proposed a new code of warfare in which all wars between the Greek city-states would be civil wars, with the stipulation that t he defeated could not be enslaved or subjected to occupation or dishonored whereas wars with barbarians 13 References to Isocrates are cited from Daws on, Doyne. The Origins of Western Warfare. Boulder, Colorado: Westview Press, 1996. 66. The quote is taken from Isocrate’s On the Peace, a pamphlet written about 355 B.C. to curb the Athenians’ imperial ambitions. In To Nicocles, Isocrates further advises the prince to “be polemik os, “warlike,” in always being prepared for war, but eirenikos, “peacable,” in never going to war without a just cause.” 14 Dawson. 68. 15 LaCroix, W.L. War and International Ethics : Tradition and Today. Lanham, New York & London: University Press of America,1988. 31. The Greeks believed that foreigners were inferior, making it possible for them to reconcile t heir taking of the vanquished as slaves.

PAGE 16

12 were to be fought with utmost ruthlessness.16 Aristotle expressed this idea in his Politics Book VII, 14, 1333b39-1334a2: “Neit her should men study war with a view to the enslavement of those who do not deserve to be ensla ved; but first of all they should provide against their own enslavement, and in the second place obtain empire for the good of the governed, and not for t he sake of exercising a general despotism, and in the third plac e they should seek to be masters only over those who deserve to be slaves.”17 Ironically, Aristotle’s pupil Alexander the Great created a Hellenistic empire that not only spread Greek cult ure and influence to the “barbarians” but had the unforeseen effect of lessening t he sharp distinctions drawn between them by the earlier philosophers. This more cosmopolitan view was reflected in the philosophical movement known as St oicism, which had many supporters in the Greco-Roman world, incl uding the early Ch ristian theologians. The basis of Stoicism was that nature and the universe were governed by the laws of reason. It significantly influenced the thought of Marcus Tullius Cicero, a great Roman statesman and orator (106-43 B.C.), w hose writings on war ethics had an enormous impact on future just war theorie s. He argued that the Stoic idea of a universal natural order should be the sour ce of all human laws and communities. In one of his clearest statements on this concept, he wrote, “that law was neither a thing contrived by the genius of man, nor established by any decree of the 16Dawson, 71. Dawson notes that Plato hoped this would make the Greeks unite in slave raids against barbarian territories, bringing more peace and cooperation between the city-states. 17 Aristotle. The Politics and The Constitution of Athens. trans. Jonathan Barnes, ed. Stephen Everson Cambridge: Cambridge Un iversity Press, 1996. 188.

PAGE 17

13 people, but a certain eternal principle, which governs the entire universe.”18 He applied this principle to war between states in his treatise On Duties : “Then, too, in the case of a state in its external re lations, the rights of war must be strictly observed. For since there are two ways of settling a dispute: first, by discussion; second; by physical force; and since the forme r is characteristic of man, the latter of the brute, we must resort to force onl y in case we may not avail ourselves of discussion. The only excuse, therefore, for going to war is that we may live in peace unharmed; and when the victory is won, we should spare those who have not been blood-thirsty and barbar ous in their warfare.” 19 This statement, among others, la id the groundwork for subsequent formulations of the two basic tenets of just war theory: jus ad bellum (just cause) and jus in bello (just conduct.) Two im portant principles of jus ad bellum that he espoused were that just wars could only be waged by those with the right authority (such as states) and that a formal declaration of war was required: “As for war, humane laws touching it are drawn up in the fetial code of the Roman People under all the guarantees of religion; and from this it may be gathered that no war is just, unless it is entered 18 The Treatises of M.T. Cicero, trans. C. D. Yonge. London: George Bell and sons, 1876. 431, quoted in Holmes, Robert L. On War and Morality. Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press, 1989. 154. 19 Cicero, Marcus Tullius. De Officiis, trans. Walter Miller. Loeb Edition. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1913, Book I.34. The Stoi c Legacy to the Renaissance. 5 January 2002.

PAGE 18

14 upon after an official demand for sa tisfaction has been submitted or warning has been given and a fo rmal declaration made.” 20 Christian Reflections on Just War The purpose of all wars is peace. Saint Augustine of Hippo The gradual decline of paganism in the Roman Empire through the fourth century coincided with the elevation of Chri stians to positions of power. However, after Constantine’s acceptance of Christi anity as the state religion, Rome began its long and ultimately unsuccessful struggl e to stem the tide of aggression by the Huns, Vandals and Goths along its borders. T he Empire’s decline led many of its citizens to return to paganism, procla iming that Christianity’s ascendancy had angered Rome’s gods. As the situation becam e more perilous the early Christian pacifist motive gave way to the realization that it would be necessary to take up arms to defend against the never ending onslaught. Saint Augustine, considered my many to be the father of modern just war theory, took on the monum ental task of reconciling the peaceful precepts of Jesus to the political realities of his era: “Like Plato and Cicero, Augustine saw war as a fact of life. Unlike them, he never saw it as an honorable, let alone glorious activity. Nor was Augustine’s just war theory simply a Christianization of Cicero’s natural law thinking…..Augustine struggled to synthesize the rigorous 20 Cicero, Book I.36.

PAGE 19

15 demands of Christian love with a keen under standing of political realities and a pessimistic view of human nature.”21 After becoming Bishop of Hippo in No rth Africa, Augustine strove to find answers to this dilemma in the Scriptures. His deep-seated pessimism about human nature stemmed from his belief in the fall of Adam and Eve, which he assumed was the cause of all war and created in him a worldview that was inhabited by the saved and the damned. T he latter inhabited the “City of Man” whereas the saved lived in the “City of Go d.” Developing Cicero’s concept of just war, Augustine set down the first condition that the sole right to wage war must be given by the proper author ity. His second condition was that war must be fought with the intention of re-establishing a just peace: “Even wicked men wage war to maintain the peace of their own circle, and wish that if possible all men belonged to them, that a ll men and things might serve but one head, and might either through love or fear yiel d themselves to peace with him.”22 His major break from Cicero and the Greek philosophers was his repudiation of glory as a proper justification for war. He saw warfare as the greatest of all evils, asking “Why allege to me the mere names and words of “glory” and “victory”? Tear off the disguise of wild delusion, and look at the naked deeds; weigh them naked, judge them naked.”23 21 Adenay, Bernard T. Just War, Political R ealism, and Faith. Metuchen, N.J. & London: The American Theological Library Association, 1988. 22Augustine, The City of God, Marcus Dods, trans ., Great Books of the We stern World, vol. 18. Chicago: Encyclopedia Britannica, 1957, Bk. X II, Ch. 22, 357. Quoted in Adeney, p. 30. 23 Augustine, III, Ch. 13, 174.

PAGE 20

16 Secular Revisions I saw in the whole Christian world a lice nse of fighting at which even barbarous nations might blush. Wars were begun on tr ifling pretexts or none at all, and carried on without any reference of law, Divine or human." --Hugo Grotius The disintegration of Rome into wa rring factions led to a period of centuries during which just war theory was largely ignored. Later theorists, most importantly Thomas Aquinas, Hugo Grot ius and Francisco di Vitoria built on Augustine’s model to develop a set of rules and regulations that promoted the proper conduct of war, leading to a clearer delineation between jus ad bellum and jus in bello principles. This latter set of pr inciples added another facet to the theory by requiring that the agents of wa r be held responsible for their actions.24 The rules of just cause remained basica lly the same during this period: having just cause, being declared by the right authority, and having peace as the goal. However, the jus in bello principle of discriminati on, concerning who were the legitimate targets of war, became an im portant part of the tradition during this time. Although Aquinas was a religious thinker, he began the process of secularizing just war doctrine by revita lizing Aristotle’s thoughts in his seminal work Summa Theologica to create the theologica l system upon which the modern Catholic Church is based. He re, he defined natural law as something that could be discerned without divine in spiration, stating that “the rule and measure of human acts is the reason, whic h is the first principle of human acts." 24 Mosely, Alex. “Just War Theory”, The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2001 15 June 2002. < http://www.utm.edu/ rese arch/iep/j/justwar.htm >

PAGE 21

1725 He used this law to refine Augustine’ s precepts for just war by using reason alone. Also, the “doctrine of double e ffect”, a rule of conduct that proved valuable in later just war thinking, was often attributed to Aquinas because of his argument that “Nothing hinders one act fr om having two effects, only one of which is intended, while the ot her is beside the intention.”26 Simply put, the doctrine maintained that it may be pe rmissible to perform a good act with the knowledge that bad consequences will ensue but that it is always wrong intentionally to do a bad act for the sake of good consequences that will ensue. Later theologians, particularly the Jesuit priest Jean Pierre Gury, developed this principle, making it applicable to a host of moral and theological issues. However, it was Francisco de Vitoria in the 16th century who first applied it to the jus in bello question of how to treat non-combat ants in war. In his lecture De indis he considered the problem of violence committed by the conquistadors against Indians during their conquest of Peru. He concluded that the Indians had rights equal to the Spaniards and could not be tr eated as inferior beings that could be exploited and enslaved. This led to the creation of jus gentium or the law of nations, establishing international no rms of behavior among nations based on natural law. In response to the misery brought about by improvements in military technology combined with the voracious power struggles between monarchs during the Renaissance, de Vitoria, along with fellow Scholastic Francisco 25 Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologica First Part of the Second Part, Q. 90, trans. Fathers of the English Dominican Province, (Benziger Bros. Edition, 1947) 15 June 2002. http://www.ccel.org/a/aquinas/summa/FS/FS090.html#FSQ90OUTP1 26 Aquinas, Second Part of the Second Part, Q. 67.

PAGE 22

18 Suarez, added further conditions for just war: first, that the means employed in the fighting of war should be proportionat e to the ends; second that all peaceful alternatives should be exhausted; and th ird, that there should a reasonable hope of victory. There are opposing camps on the issue of who was the “father of international law”, Vitoria or Hugo Grotius. Most secular writ ers side with Grotius, the author of the famous treatise De Jure Belli ac Pacis (On the Rights of War and Peace). Here, he attempted to ground just war precepts on natural law rather than Christian doctrine, recognizing two alternatives to divine law: the law of nature and the law of nat ions. Influenced by Aquinas, Grotius’ law of nature was derived from universal truths under stood through human reason. The law of nations was derived from customary prac tices and relationships between states in the real world.27 Just War Theory in the Twentieth Century War is so awful that it makes us cynica l about the possibility of restraint, and then it is so much worse that it makes us indignant at the absence of restraint. Our cynicism testifies to the defectiveness of the war convention, and our indignation to its reality and strength. — Michael Walzer Just war theory was further codifi ed into international law when two documents were issued in the wake of Wo rld War II: the Nuremburg and United Nations Charters. The first charter est ablished the conditions constituting unjust acts in the course of war. 28 The United Nations Charte r, especially Article 51, 27 Roosevelt, Grace. “A Brief History of the Ques t for Peace: Pacifism and Just War Theory in Europe from the 16th to the 20th Centuries.” Global Policy Forum. 23 June 2003. < http://www.globalpolicy.org/ resource/unhist/jinx1.htm > 28 Nuremberg Trial Proceedings Vol 1. Aval on Project. Yale Law School. 9 March 2003. < http://www.yale.edu/lawweb /avalon/imt/proc/discrep.htm >

PAGE 23

19 declared the right of sovereign nations to self-defense. However, it was largely ignored as a theory until t he mid-twentieth century, when it became a cornerstone for arguments against the nuclear arms race and the Vietnam War. In response to the threat of nuclear wa r during the height of the Cold War, The United States Catholic Conference issued The Challenge of Peace: God’s Promise and Our Response in 1983 a comprehensive evaluation of just war doctrine condemning the use of nuclear weapons and laying out plans for shaping a peaceful world. Its just wa r criteria are shown in Table 1. Table 1: Just War Criteria jus ad bellum : why and when recourse to war is permissible 1. Just Cause War is permissible only to confront a ‘real and certain danger’ To preserve innocent life, to preserve conditions necessary for decent human existence and to secure basic human rights. 2. Competent Authority War must be declared by those with responsibility for public order, not by private groups or individuals. 3. Comparative Justice Do the rights and values involved justify killing? In other words, which side is sufficiently ‘right’ in the dispute, and are the values at stake critical enough o override the presumption against war? 4. Right Intention This has two parts. In just cause, war can be intended only for the reasons set forth in just cause. During the conflict, it includes the pursuit of peace and reconciliation and avoiding unnecessarily destructive acts or unreasonable conditions. 5. Last resort All peaceful alternatives must be exhausted. Here the Bishops stress the importance of the United Nations as a governing body that can help alleviate some of the problems inherent in these criteria. 6. Probability of Success The purpose of these criteria, although difficult to apply, is to prevent irrational resort to forc e or hopeless resistance when the outcome of either will clearly be disproportionate or futile. 7 Proportionality The damage to be inflicted and the costs incurred must be proportionate to the good expected by taking up arms. jus in bello : how the war should be conducted 1. Discrimination Requirement to avoid k illing non-combatants, a criterion that is becoming harder to comply with. 2. Proportionality Each action must be judged according to the level of force required, with the least possible force used to achieve victory.

PAGE 24

20 However, modern just war t heory owes a great debt to Just and Unjust Wars Michael Walzer’s attempt to estab lish a constructivist (as opposed to realist) secular and modern version of ju st war based on linking states’ rights to individual rights rather than the rights of princes as ear thly representatives of God’s authority: The rights of states rest on the cons ent of their members. But this is consent of a special sort. State rights are not constituted through a series of transfers from individual men and women to the sovereign . what actually happens . [is that] ov er a long period of time, shared experiences and cooperative activity of many different kinds shape a common life . most states do stand guard over the community of their citizens, at least to some degree: that is why we assume the justice of their defensive wars.29 Through this linkage, Walzer sets up a “legalist paradigm” of six principles that must be shared by states in the in ternational arena: 1. There exists an international society of sovereign states. 2. This international so ciety has laws that est ablishes the right of its members – above all, the rights of te rritorial integrity and political sovereignty 3. Any use of force or imminent thr eat of force by one state against the political sovereignty of another cons titutes aggression and is a criminal act. 4. Aggression justifies two kinds of violent response: a war of self-defense by the victim and a war of law enfor cement by the victim and any other member of international society. 5. Nothing but aggression can justify war. 6. Once the aggressor state has been mili tarily repulsed, it can also be punished.30 However, he argues that in some cases, any or all of these principles may need to be violated, even advocating the use of “pre-emptive” attacks in 29 Michael Walzer. Just and Unjust Wars: A Moral Ar gument with Historical Illustrations, Second edition, New York: Basic Books, 1992. 53–4. 30 Walzer.,61–2.

PAGE 25

21 situations where there is a manifest int ent to injure, proof of preparation that shows the intent to be a danger, or a general situation in which the risk of defeat is greatly increased if war is delayed. O ne example is the Israeli strike on Egypt, June 5, 1967 during the Six-Day War, just after Egypt had declared its intention of extermination. 31 He also revises earlier discussions of the “doctrine of double effect” by offering three conditions that must be met to reconcile effects (such as the killing of non-combatants) emanating from actions made with just intent. First, the direct effect must be morally acceptable (f or example, the desired result is the destruction of a legitimate military target.) Second, the actor’s intention must be good, and the bad effect not intentional. In this case, the actor should not use the bad effect as a means to the ends. For example, it is wrong to target civilians for the purpose of weakening an enemy’s reso lve. Third, the good effect must be sufficiently good to justify the bad effect. Here again, he advocates the violation of one of the principles, namely th e second condition, by proposing his controversial notion of “supreme emer gency”, in which unjust means may be justified in rare cases, using the exam ple of Britain’s car pet bombing of Dresden as justifiable because of the need to com bat the “abominable ev il” of the Hitler regime. Nonetheless, he concludes that this conduct must be eschewed when the aim is reached, with immediate reinstatem ent of the just war criteria that were violated. In his review of Walzer ’s book, Gilbert Meilaender describes how Britain resolved this dilemma after World War II: 31 Walzer. 81.

PAGE 26

22 After the bombing of German cities had succeeded and the war had been won, Britain needed to find a way to reinstate the moral rules it had—in the moment of supreme emergency—overridden. Walzer interprets the dishonoring of Arthur Harris as such a reinstatement. Harris had directed the British Bomber Co mmand’s campaign of terror against German cities. He had, it is perhaps not too strong to say, been good enough to be on the right side but not too good to do what was needed in Britain’s time of peril. After the war he expected his re ward: public honor. He received none, however, and finally left Britain and returned to his native Rhodesia. By dishonoring him, Britain dissociat ed itself from what had been done—it reinstated the moral code. We may, Walz er grants, feel t hat this is not quite fair to Harris, but it may be the best a people can manage.32 Brian Orend incorporates Walzer’s human rights approach to launch a fresh interpretation of just war theory based on the works of Immanuel Kant. The importance of this thesis lies in its emphasis on an aspect of just war that is virtually ignored by mo st other theorists: the jus post bellum principles applying to the end process of creating a just peace. He divides th is final component into short term and long term principles. T he short term principles deal with the termination of conflicts as they relate to specific wars. The long term principles have a more ambitious agenda, the progressi ve elimination of war in general. This dichotomy represents the inherent t ension between what Orend believes are the two necessary ingredients for the comp lete just war theory that the Kantian method provides: a comprehensive theoretic al framework and a set of principles 32 Meilaender, Gilbert. 2000. Michael Walzer: Just and Unjust Wars (1977). First Things, 101 (2000):52-53. Online. Internet. 9 March 2003. Available http://www.firstthings.com/ftissues /ft0003/articles/ walzer.html

PAGE 27

23 for practical application. Table 2 complete s the picture of just war theory as it stands today. 33 Table 2: Just War Criteria (addition) jus post bellum : when and how war is concluded 1. Just Cause for termination A state has just cause to seek termi nation of the just war in question if there has been a reasonable vindication of those rights whose violation grounded the resort to war in the first place. 2. Right Intention A state must intend to carry out the process of war termination only in terms of those principles contained in the other jus post bellum rules. Revenge is strictly ruled out as an animating force. Furthermore, the just state in question must commit itself to symmetry and equal application with regard to the investigat ion and prosecution of any jus in bello war crimes. 3. Public declaration and legitimate authority The terms of the peace must be publicly proclaimed by a legitimate authority. 4. Discrimination In setting the terms of the peace, the just and victorious state is to differentiate between the political and military leaders, the soldiers and the civilian population within the aggressor regime. 5. Proportionality Terms of peace are propo rtional to reasonable rights vindication and do not violate the human rights of the populace, thereby negating the concept of unconditional surrender. 33 Orend, Brian. War and International Justice: A Kantian Perspective. Waterloo & Ontario, anada: Wilfrid Laurier University Press, 2000. 269-70.

PAGE 28

24 Feminist Analysis of Just War Introduction Where are the women? Cynthia Enloe A commentary written by journalist Cy nthia Peters in the online magazine ZNET evokes the frustration that femini sts feel about the roles that women are designated to play in wartime. To illust rate this point, she quotes the headline of a satirical piece in Onion Magazine: “N ot Knowing What Else to Do, Woman Bakes American Flag Cake.” Continuing with the story, she quotes: “Having already donated blood, mailed a check to the Red Cross, and sent a letter of thanks to the New York Fire Department, she settled on the red, white, and blue creation as her next response to the terror.”34 Lucinda Peach describes a possible r eason for this frustration: “Women remain largely absent from ethical and policy debates regarding when to go to war, how to fight a war, and whether reso rting to war is morally justifiable.”35 One explanation for this absence is that t he making, waging and concluding of wars has traditionally been male-centric. As t he previous chapter shows, just war theory follows this tradition by being almo st exclusively written by and for men. Within the time between the two Gulf wars with Iraq, ther e have been very few 34 Peters, Cynthia. “Women’s Patriotic Role,” ZNET. (2001).. 23 March 2003. 35 Peach, Lucinda. “An Alternative to Pacifi sm? Feminism and Just-War Theory,” Bringing Peace Home.: Feminism, Violence and Nature, ed. K.J. Warren and D.L. Cady, Bloomington and Indianapolis: Indiana University Press, 1996. 196.

PAGE 29

25 feminist voices to be heard in these mainstream debates, wit h the exception of Jean Bethke Elshtain, who has written several books on various theoretical and specific aspects of this topic. However, it is possible to construct a feminist vision of just war and peace by examin ing the variety of feminist based approaches to ethics that have developed in response to the underrating of women’s moral experience. The first section of this chapter provides an historical overview of feminist mo ral approaches, concentrating primarily on those issues related to war and peace. The second section delineates feminist critiques of contemporary applications of just war theory. The chapter concludes that contemporary just war theory lacks the depth and breadth necessary to confront issues such as intraand non-state forms of violence. Feminist Ethics Feminist ethics is born of women's refusals to endure with grace the arrogance, indifference, hostility, and damage of oppressively sexist environments. —Claudia Card Despite the fractured nature of t he “feminist critique” of ethics36, all of the various discourses ultimately “attempt to revise, reformulate, or rethink those aspects of traditional western ethics that depreciate or devalue women's moral experience” to “create a gender-equal ethics, a moral theory that generates non36 For example, the acknowledgment that feminist scho larship is a “site of active political struggle” in a “fractured and heavily cont ested discourse” found in R.B. J. Walker. 1992. "Gender and Critique in the Theory of International Relation s," in V. Spike Peterson (ed.), Gendered States: Feminist (Re)Visions of International Relations Theory Boulder, CO, & London p. 179.

PAGE 30

26 sexist moral principles, policies, and practices.” 37 These discourses are most often divided into three broad categories: Feminist Empiricism Feminist empiricists argue that gender-biased science only creates “bad epistemology,” arguing that once these bias es are eliminated (by throwing more women and other minorities into the mix), a value-neutral epistemology will ensue to liberate knowledge. This argum ent coincides with liberal feminism, which contends that gender equality can be gained by winning equal access to the educational and political rights enjoy ed by men within t he existing system. There are several critiques of liberal femini sm worth noting. First, other feminists argue that this position accepts male va lues as human values and assumes that women can and should aspire to be like men. Another critique closely related to the first is that “male” standards are valued higher than t hose associated with women, such as interdependence and caring. A third critique cites its emphasis of individual rights over the common good. However, this feminist viewpoint remains popular with many women and wo men’s organizations that work to promote gender equality throughout the world. Due to their efforts, more and more women are inhabiting spaces that were formerly the exclusive enclaves of men and demanding equal positions of resp ect (as evidenced by the growing participation of women in politics and the mi litary in the United States.) Liberal feminists usually reject the idea that women are more peaceful than men by 37 Tong, Rosemarie, "Feminist Ethics", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2002 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), 23 March 2003. < http://plato.stanford. edu/entries/feminismethics/ >

PAGE 31

27 nature and argue that to effect change; they need to demand an equal voice and role in international decision-making pos itions, including roles in the military. Standpoint Feminism Standpoi nt feminists assert that knowledge is socially constructed. They view women's marginal position in soci ety as a potential advantage rather than merely as an oppressive situation for women. They argue from the Marxist position that a socially oppressed cla ss has valuable knowledge that is unavailable to the privileged class by the mere fact that it is oppressed, and therefore attempts to inco rporate the standpoint s of other marginalized groups in its quest for knowledge. One argument fo r the value of this theory is that “knowledge which emerges from women’s ex periences ‘on the margins’ of world politics is actually more neutral and critic al because it is not complicit with, or blinded by, existing institutions and power relations.”38 Most standpoint feminists view war from the perspective that ex clusion from power leads women to be more peaceable than men because they must bargain from a position of weakness. Within standpoint, the “ethics of care” approach is the predominant theory that speaks to the issues of war and peace. This theory was born when Carol Gilligan published a very influential book in 1982 called In a Different Voice, where she described her ex periments on how men and women react to various hypothetical situations. This book wa s prompted by her professor Lawrence Kohlberg’s contention that there were six stages of moral development 38 True, Jacqui. “Feminism.” Theories of Internat ional Relation., eds. Burchill, S. and A. Linklater. New York: St. Martin’s Press, 1995,1996. 215.

PAGE 32

28 concluding that only men could reac h the highest stage of an “impartial, universalist, and principled perspec tive: the ethics of justice.39 In reply, her book proposed that Kohlberg’s results were mistaken because they were based on “male-biased” methodology that did not take into account the possibility of different kinds of ethical behaviour. Ra ther, her study revealed that men and women have fundamentally different approaches to morality: women focus more on ‘care’ and men on ‘justice’. Women bas e their morality on relationships and responsibility, whereas men focus on the tr aditional western ethics of rationalism, Kantianism, and liberalism. Nel Noddings expanded on Gilligan’s “ethics of care”, using an approach emphasizing particular others as the objects of care: To act as one-caring ... is to act with special regard for the particular person in a concrete situation ... she acts in a nonrule-bound fashion in behalf of the cared for ... [An ethic of care] does not attempt to reduce the need for human judgment with a series of “Thou shalts” and “Thou shalt nots”. Rather, it recognizes and calls forth human judgment across a wide range of fact and feeling, and it allows for situations and conditions in which judgment (in the im personal, logical sense) may properly be put aside in favor of faith and commitment.40 Along this vein, maternal feminists su ch as Sara Ruddick, Virginia Held, and Caroline Whitbeck, commemorate the feminine characterist ics of mothering and parenting, arguing that “the experience of mothering, of caring for others could serve as an important ethical model for civic participation as well as a 39Hutchings, Kimberly. “Ethics, Feminism, and Intern ational Affairs.” eds. Coicaud, Jean-Marc and Daniel Warner. Ethics and International Affairs. New York: United Nations University Press, 2001. 200. 40 Noddings, Nell. Caring: A Feminine Approach to Ethics and Moral Education Berkely: University of Californi a Press, 1984, 24-5.

PAGE 33

29 corrective to citizenship based on military service.”41 Developing this proposal, Ruddick makes the case that mo thering and war are incompatible: When maternal thinking takes upon itse lf the critical perspective of a feminist standpoint, it reveals a contradiction between mothering and war. Mothering begins in bi rth and promises life; military thinking justifies organized, deliber ate deaths. A mother preserves the bodies, nurtures the psychic growth and disciplines the conscience of children; although the military trains its soldiers to survive the situations it puts them in, it also deliberately endangers their bodies, minds and consciences in the name of victory and abstract causes.42 Feminists and non-feminists alike crit icize these approaches for their emphasis on the specific relationshi ps engendered by individual human relationships, arguing that they don’t trans late into a general model that can be used to describe other types of relations hips such as those between communities and groups. Ruddick herself concedes that she might be “over-idealizing mothers, unnecessarily ex cluding men and nonbiological mothers from maternal work, and underemphasizing the differences that exist among mothers, some of whom find themselves "mothering" under extremely oppressive circumstances.”43 Other critics argue that this stress on personal relationships creates a “partialist” approach in the ethics of care that mu st be integrated with the universal and rational ethics related to the “justice” orientation: “This means that unless exponents of a personal ethics of care w anted to take the hard-nosed view that 41 True, 215. 42 Hutchings, 202. 43 Tong, Rosemarie, "Feminist Ethics", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2002 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), 2 March 2003. < http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/ fall2002/entries/feminism-ethics/. >

PAGE 34

30 we never have any moral duties and responsi bilities to those with whom we have no personal relationships, they would still need to devise and defend some ethical principles to govern our relati onship with strangers. . An adequate ethics needs impartiality as well as care.”44 Nonetheless, standpoint feminists’ emphasis on particularity and personal expe rience creates the ability to identify with and take responsibility for the suffe ring of others, as seen in growing movements such as Women in Black, begun in 1988 by Israeli women empathizing with the plight of Palestini an women by protesting against Israel’s occupation of the West Bank and Gaza. Also, their emphasis on the necessity of incorporating multiple “standpoi nts” allows for ethical c onsideration of the diverse perspectives of parties to any dispute or conflict.45 Postmodern Feminism “Postmodern feminism” is not easily definable, incorporating so many diverging viewpoints as to make the term almost meaningless as well as unfashionable in some circles. However, this paper characterizes it as a reaction against the scientific method that disput es the definition of reality from objective/subjective or empirical/normati ve stances. Rather, many of these feminists view reality as structured by discourse representing relations of power and domination, agreeing that the male/female dichotomy is a main categorizing force in our society. They criticize the structure of this society and the dominant patriarchal order within which wom en and other marginalized people are 44 Kuhse, Helga. Caring: Nurses, Women and Et hics. Maldon, MA: Blackwell, 1997.137-38. 45 Hutchings. 204.

PAGE 35

31 perceived as the Other. Furthermore, they perceive any attempts to label their viewpoints as essentialist fallacies. As postmodern feminists see it, all attempts to provide a single explanation for women's oppression not only will fail but should also fail. They will fail because there is no one entity, "Woman," upon whom a label may be fixed. Women are individuals, each with a unique story to tell about a particular self. Moreover, any single explanation for "Woman's" oppression should fail from a feminist point of view, for it would be yet another instance of so-call "phallogocent ric" thought: that is, the kind of "male thinking" that insists on telli ng as absolute truth one and only one story about reality. Women must, in the estimation of postmortem feminists reveal their differences to each other so that they can better resist the patriarchal tendency to cent er, congeal, and cement thought into a rigid "truth" that always was, is, and forever will be.46 Although not known as a “postmodern” feminist, Jean Bethke Elshtain uses a Foucauldian linguistic constructivism to examine the traditional roles played by women and men in war, concluding that they are socially constructed by the dominant historical narratives about the ma le “Just Warrior”/ hero who fights for the greater good and the female “Beautiful Soul” who pla ys the maternal support figure in need of ma le protection. To take up war-as-discourse compels us to recognize the powerful sway of received narratives and reminds us that the concepts through which we think about war, peace, and politics get repeated endlessly, shaping debates, c onstraining consideration of alternatives, often reassuring us that things cannot really be much different than they are. As we nod an automatic "yes" when we hear the truism (though we may despair of the truth it tells) that "there have always been war," we acknowledge tacitly that "there have always been war stories," for wars are deeded to us as texts. We cannot identify "war itself" as an entity apart fr om a tradition 46 Tong.

PAGE 36

32 that includes poems, epics, myths, official histories, and first-person accounts, as well as articulated theories.47 Elshtain’s war-as-discourse analysis pr ecludes the supposition that there is a link between women and peace, propos ing instead that women’s attitudes about war and peace can differ substantiall y depending on such factors as time periods and cultures.48 She suggests that this link age belies the fact that peace feminists are usually greatly outnumbered by the majority of women who support the wars that their nations wage, citing the example of women in the suffragist movement who rushed to support the war ef fort at the outbreak of the First World War while others handed out white feather s as symbols of cowardice to young men not in uniform. 49 In Gender and ‘Postmodern’ War, Robin Schott proposes that “postmodern understandings of persons, states, and politics …render an event based conception of war inadequate, especia lly insofar as gender is taken into account.”50 47 Elshtain, Jean Bethke. Women and War. Chicago and London: The University of Chicago Press, 1987. 32. One example of this use of narrative to compel the perpetuation of the Just Warrior\Beautiful Soul motifs is the story of Aida Lafuente, a young woman who fought on the side of the insurrectionists in the Spanish revolution of 1934. Following the revolt, prorevolutionist poets, writers and politicians m ade her a symbol of womanhood and purity to counteract the uncomfortable image of a woman wa rrior. (Bunk, Brian. “Revolutionary Warrior and Gendered Icon: Aida Lafuente and the Spanish Revolution of 1934.” Journal of Women’s History, 15.2 (2003): 99-122. 48 Berkham, Joyce.. “Feminism, War and Peace Polit ics: The Case of World War I.” eds. Elshtain, J.B. and S. Tobias.. Women, Militarism & War: Es says in History, Politics, and Social Theory. Maryland: Rowman and Littlefield Publishers, Inc., 1990. 141. 49 Elshtain, Women and War. 140. 50 Cuomo, Chris. “War is Not Just An Even t: Reflections on the Significance of Everyday Violence.” Hypatia 11.4 (1996): < http://gw.softlineweb.com.proxy.usf.edu/record.a sp?msel_from=0&msel_to=9&preview=&move= &returnPage=list.asp&articleID=114302&recNum=1 >

PAGE 37

33 Feminist Critiques of Just War Theory But history, real solemn history, I c annot be interested in... I read it a little as a duty, but it tells me nothing that does not either vex or weary me. The quarrels of popes and kings, with wars or pestilences, in every page; the men all so good for nothing, and hardly any women at all--it is very tiresome. —Jane Austen's Catherine Morland in Northanger Abbey What are the criticisms that fe minists have about just war theory? Although few feminist scholars explicitly focus on this topic (Elshtain, Cohn & Ruddick in particular), others address sim ilar issues within the broader scope of war and peace. Lucinda Peach groups thes e criticisms around several concerns: “its close relationship with realism, its failu re to insist that all criteria have been satisfied in accordance with rigorous standards, especially in relation to attempting nonviolent alternatives; its tendency to abstract and to dichotomize reality in accordance with gendered distinct ions; and the priority it accords to the state and to state authority vis--vis the individual.”51 All of these are legitimate concerns, but she misses one very important criticism of just war theory: it addresses war as a discrete event rather than a continuing presence in modern culture. Realism Realists concentrate on states and their power relationships as the most important aspect of world politics. Hans Morgenthau, a primary architect of this theory, assumed that “statesmen thin k and act in terms of interest defined as power,” creating a world system with an “a stounding continuity in foreign power which makes American, British, or Russian foreign policy appear as an 51 Peach, 195.

PAGE 38

34 intelligible, rational continuum, by and larg e consistent within itself, regardless of the different motives, preferences, and intellectual and moral qualities of successive statesmen.”52 Sara Ruddick and Carol Cohn, identifying themselves anti-war feminists, believe that those who practice this type of politics view war as an inescapable part of this system. T hey further declare that although just war theorists use normative methods to analyze the justice of wars, their theory resides within the parameters of this realist assumption of war’s inevitability, therefore accepting war as a practice Cohn and Ruddick, on the other hand, reject war as a practice (while disti nguishing themselves from pacifists by acknowledging those among them who c ontinue to support particular military campaigns.)53 However, Elshtain distinguishes the sp irit of just war theory as “a way of thinking that refuses to s eparate politics from ethics” 54, from the realist world where “no children are ever born, and nobody ever dies…There are states, and they are what is.”55 She argues that just war thinki ng is not inextricably linked to the realist paradigm, transcending the use of its rhetoric by realist states to 52 Hans Morgenthau, Politics among Nations, 5,6, quoted in Women, Gender, and World Politics: Perspectives, Policies, and Prospects, eds P.R. Beckman and F. D’Amico. Westport, Connecticut & London: Bergin & Garvey, 1994. 17. 53 Cohn and Ruddick refer to these feminists as te mporary anti-militarists because although they support military action, they “oppose war as a practi ce, mourn the suffering of all of wars’ victims, and, in the midst of war, imagine the details of a future culture of peace.” Cohn, Carol & Sara Ruddick. “A Feminist Ethical Perspective on We apons of Mass Destruction.” to be published in Ethics and Weapons of Mass Dest ruction, Steven Lee and Sohail Hashmi, eds., under review at Cambridge University Press. 14 February 2004. < http://www.ksg.har vard.edu/wappp/research/w orking/cohn_ruddick.pdf > 54 Elshtain, Jean Bethke. “Just War and Humanitarian Intervention.” Ideas, 8.2 (2002): 4. 55 Elshtain. Women and War. 91.

PAGE 39

35 legitimize their struggles fo r power, asserting that “tr aditional just-war theory is not problematic so much because it is itse lf realist as because it is anachronistic and no longer able to provide meaningful limits to war in a world governed by realist assumptions.”56 For her, Michael Walzer’s argument that in the face of “immeasurable evil” (i.e. Nazism), a “s upreme emergency” exists allowing the use of unjust means to achieve victory is a clear example of how realists violate the principles of just war for their own purposes.57 On the other hand, she maintains that “when a wound as griev ous as that of September 11 has been inflicted on a body politic, it would be t he height of moral irresponsibility… were the relevant governments to fail to res pond” by applying just war theory to exercise armed force in a responsible and limited manner.58 Failure to Consider Alternatives to War Just war theory clearly states that a gov erning authority must reasonably exhaust all other diplomatic and non -military options for securing peace before resorting to force. However, The United States Bishops’ treatise The Challenge of Peace is the only document on just war that at tempts to fully delineate nonviolent alternatives to war and escalation of c onflicts. It is an impassioned reaction and statement against the use of nuclear weapons, and one of the firs t appeals for just peacemaking as an alternative to war: 56 Peach, 196. 57 Peach. 196. 58 Elshtain, Jean Bethke. “Luther’s Lamb: When and How to Fight a Just War.” Common Knowledge, 8.2 (2002): 304-309.

PAGE 40

36 We are the first generation since G enesis with the power to virtually destroy God's creation. We cannot remain silent in the face of such danger. Peacemaking is not an optional co mmitment. It is a requirement of our faith. We are called to be peacemak ers, not by some movement of the moment, but by our Lord Jesus.59 For Walzer, these statements prove his contention that a last resort could turn into “an endlessly receding possibilit y, invoked mostly by people who would prefer never to resist aggr ession with force. After all, there is always something else to do, another diplomat ic note, another meeting.”60 To feminists, this position underscores the fact that “last resort” criter ia are seldom fully considered before hostilities are instigated. According to Elshtain, “the American public seems at this point so inured to the rather r outine use of American bombing in foreign policy situations that these actions scarc ely register on the r adar screen most of the time.”61 Abstract Thought/Dichotomized Thinking Feminist analyses “specifically reveal how abstraction in the application of just war theory has resulted in (1) a neglec t of the horrors of war and its effects on individual bodies;(2) a perception of t he enemy as “Other”; and (3) a fixation on principles of justice and rights rather than the needs a nd interests of specific persons in particular conflicts.”62 59 The Challenge of Peace: God's Promise and Our Response. (1983) Washington, D.C.: USCC, par. 333. 60 Michael Waltzer, “Perplexed”, New Repub lic (1991): 14 quoted in Peach, 197. 61 Elshtain, Just War and Humanitarian Intervention, p. 20. 62 Peach, 198.

PAGE 41

37 For instance, a feminist former RAF officer in the Persian Gulf conflict illustrates the moment in which she re cognized the duality in which the suffering of individuals was viewed: Around one week into the “conflict” pr oper, by which time we had lost several crews from our base during bombi ng raids, I heard the voices of some downed aircrew on CNN—two of whom were my colleagues. I was overjoyed that they had survived. Lat er, as I watched t he video footage of their battered faces, and the news t eams discussed the Iraqi breaking of the Geneva Convention through beati ng up downed aircrew, I realized how utterly stupid the whole thing was. We had been “bombing the shit” out of Iraq for days. There were obv iously many Iraqis being killed. But beating up captured aircrew who had ju st bombed you was “barbaric” and “against the rules.”63 This dichotomy is also apparent in the American media’s coverage of September 11’s victims as opposed to t he civilian victims of the war in Afghanistan. When the New York Times put a human face to the thousands who perished in the Twin Towers by featur ing vignettes with pictures and minibiographies listing the victims’ inte rests and families, they created an ineradicable image by visualizing the personal aspects of the loss. Howard Zinn was deeply moved by those intimate glim pses of the real people lost in the tragedy, speculating “what if all those Americans who declare their support for Bush's "war on terrorism" could see, instead of those elusive symbols--Osama bin Laden, Al Qaeda--the real human beings who have died under our bombs?”64 63 Roper, Lynne. 2001. “Feminism is NOT Pacifi sm: A Personal View of the Politics of War.” Feminist Media Studies, 2(1): 150-51. 64 Zinn, Howard. 2002. “The Others.” The Nation 19 March 2003. < http://www.thenation.com/doc .mhtml?i=20020211&s=zinn >

PAGE 42

38 Ira Chernus relates how President Eis enhower’s administration exploited this good/evil rhetoric in its foreign policy: Everything had to be woven into the syst em (as loosely articulated as it was) and circumscribed within its absol ute demarcations between truth and falsehood, right and wrong. Theref ore all realities had to be dichotomized; everything had to be treat ed only in relation to its absolute opposite. Dichotomizing and polarizi ng were the only path he could see leading to clarity. In political terms freedom, capitalism, and "the American way" could be meaningful only if pitted against their absolute opposites. Hence the need to construct discursively an imminent foreign and domestic "Red menace," so that the nation could be called to make a decisive choice between the opposites.65 Feminists argue that just war theory st resses the notions of just/unjust and good/evil wars, reinforcing the ability to abstract the enemy as the “Other”, making their annihilation mu ch more palatable. Further, standpoint feminists argue that its emphasis on rights and just ice promotes separation rather than connection, leading to the likelihood of more not less recourse to aggression. If, for example, the victor’s terms of justic e in the wake of the war are perceived as unduly harsh by the vanquished, will the end of war bring a true peace? “Typically”, Cohn and Rudd ick state, “‘peace’ includes official ongoing “punishment”—retributi on, reparations, dominat ion, and deprivation.”66 This is evident in Orend’s jus post bellum principles, which emphasize rights vindication and the question of punishment over mediat ion and reconciliation. Issues such 65 Chernus, Ira. 2002. General Eisenhower: Ideol ogy and Discourse. East Lansing: Michigan State University Press. 291. 66 Cohn, Carol & Sara Ruddick. “A Feminist Ethical Perspective on Weapons of Mass Destruction.” to be published in Ethics and Weapo ns of Mass Destruction, Steven Lee and Sohail Hashmi, eds., under review at Cambridge Univ ersity Press. 14 February 2004. < http://www.ksg.har vard.edu/wappp/research/w orking/cohn_ruddick.pdf >

PAGE 43

39 as war crimes trials are more comfort able within this framework than discussions of creating a just peace.67 Suppression of Individual Rights by the State Just war theory requires that a war must be endorsed by a person or entity that has the proper authority to do so, priv ileging the rights of the state over the rights of individuals in t he name of the “common good”. Government reactions to catastrophic events such as September 11, including the passing of legislation, (i.e. Patriot Act I) or th e detention of certain indivi duals based on their ethnicity (Japanese internments during World War II) within the atmosphere of war allows what Sara Ruddick calls just war’ s “unquestioning obedience as a virtue.”68 Further, just war theorists since the Peace of Westphalia have focused on the sovereign state as the only acto r, that is, the actor that plays the critical role in matters of war, ignoring the growi ng number of non-state actors in the international arena. In relation to femini st theory, especially the ethics of care, this emphasis on states over individuals fails to recognize the importance of interpersonal a well as interstate relations. War as Event According to Barbara Ehrenreich, those who study war empirically as a recurrent event speak of its “epidemic ity”—its tendency to spread in a manner corresponding to an infectious disease. In other words, as Dutch social scientist 67 An example of this mind-set is Kellogg, Davi da. 2002. “Jus Post Bellum: The Importance of War Crimes Trials.” Parameters Autumn, 87-99. 68 Peach. 201.

PAGE 44

40 Henk Houweling observes, “one of the causes of war is war itself”.69 Analogously, many feminists re fuse to regard war as a series of discrete events (threat followed by invasion, battle, then ceasefire), considering it instead as a systematic expression of the so ciety within which it resides, so that “in contrast to much just war theory, it …[does] not separ ate war from either the preparations made for it (preparations taken in the wi dest possible, including the social costs of maintaining large standing armies and the machinery of deterrence), or from its long term physical, psychologic al, socio-economic, environmental, and gendered effects.70 In fact, ethical approaches such as just war theory that “do not attend to the ways in which warfare and military practices are woven into the very fabric of life in twent y-first century technological states lead to crisis-based politics and analyses.”71 Conclusion In the just war scenario there are only two sides, the aggressor and the victim, the victor and the v anquished. However, the real world also contains an entire set of people who aren’t on either side, neither aggressor nor victim, with little or no stake in who wins or loses. According to the anthropologist William Ury, this group is the “Third Side” that can step in to resolve or lessen tensions 69 Ehrenreich, Barbara. 2003. “The Roots of War.” The Progressive 67(4): 14. 70 Cohn, Carol & Sara Ruddick. “A Feminist Ethical Perspective on Weapons of Mass Destruction.” to be published in Ethics and Weapo ns of Mass Destruction, Steven Lee and Sohail Hashmi, eds., under review at Cambridge Univ ersity Press. 14 February 2004. < http://www.ksg.har vard.edu/wappp/research/w orking/cohn_ruddick.pdf > 71 Cuomo, Chris. “War is Not Just An Even t: Reflections on the Significance of Everyday Violence.” Hypatia 11.4 (1996): < http://gw.softlineweb.com.proxy.usf.edu/record.a sp?msel_from=0&msel_to=9&preview=&move= &returnPage=list.asp&articleID=114302&recNum=1 >

PAGE 45

41 and conflicts.72 His assertion that peace is t he norm rather than war introduces the next chapter’s discussion of just peace. 72 Ury, William L. The Third Side: Why We Fight and How We Can Stop. New York: Penguin Books, 2000.

PAGE 46

42 Just Peace Theory "The third side is a kind of social immune sy stem that prevents the spread of the virus of violence."—William Ury Introduction William Ury questions the Hobbesian outl ook that only a strong government can restrain human nature’s tendency to war and violence. Drawing on the works of Frans de Waal ( Primate Behavior and Human Aggression, which questions the myth that humans are innately ag gressive) and R. Brian Ferguson ( The History of War: Fact vs. Fiction, which uses archeological evidenc e to prove that most of human history was peaceful rather than warlike), he asks how our ancestors were able to resolve conflict so successf ully for so long? He formulated his answer while performing fieldwork among tribes like the Bushmen of Kalahari, observing the way in which family, friends and the extended community intervened to resolve issues between c ontending parties. He realized that conflicts never take place in a vacuum strictly between two adversaries. “In a nutshell," Ury explains, "the third side is composed of people from the community using a certain kind of power, the power of peers, from a certain perspective, which is a perspective of common ground; supporting a certain process, which is the process of dialogue and nonviolence; and aiming for a certain product, which

PAGE 47

43 is a triple win--a solution that's good fo r the community and good for both of the parties." 73 Ury recognizes that conflict is natur al and advocates positive interaction rather than mere opposition fr om outside, providing concre te practices for “third siders” to play in bringing resolution to conf licts. Ury’s ten roles that “third siders” can play are: 1. Provider: helping people meet their frustrated needs 2. Teacher: instilling skills or attitudes to defuse tensions 3. Bridge Builder: fostering good rela tionships across potential lines of conflict 4. Mediator: helping people reconc ile their opposite interests 5. Arbiter: delineati ng the disputed rights 6. Equalizer: balancing the pow er between clashing parties 7. Healer: repairing injured relati onships and defusing wounded emotions 8. Witness: taking heed and note of early warning signs of dispute 9. Referee: establishing objective rules for conflict 10. Peace Keeper: stepping in to s eparate the fighting parties, even physically.74 How can “third-siders” work to prevent conflicts before they happen? They can be providers, teac hers and bridge-builders. Ho w do they contain wars 73 Ury, William. Must We Fight? From the Battlefield to the Schoolyard-A New Perspective on Violent Conflict & Its Prevention. New York: John Wiley & Sons, 2001. 38 74 Ury. Must We Fight

PAGE 48

44 while they are happening? They witness, referee, and act as peacekeepers. How can they resolve conflicts? They c an mediate, arbitrate, equalize and heal. As Ury notes, “No one third-side role is sufficient to stop violence. The roles constitute a series of protective safe ty nets. If one doesn’t catch the conflict and stop it from escalating, another will. T ogether, these roles constitute a systemic approach to what is, after all, a systemic problem.”75 A similar set of principles and roles are found in the ten principles espoused in the book Just Peacekeeping (included in Appendix A). Feminist Just Peace Unlike William Ury’s ten roles or Glen Stassen’s Ten Principles of Peacemaking, there are no wr itten “feminist principl es of just peace”. Liberal feminists prefer to work within the prevailing patriarchical system to win equal rights and access for marginalized groups. In keeping with this stance, most embrace just war theory, with certai n reservations. Elshtain is a strong advocate for using just war principles as long as they are not couched in realist terms. She appeals for a return to emphasis on the jus ad bellum principles founded by Saint Augustine. Neta Crawford is not quite as enamored, stating that “each conflict demands its own analysi s, which must occur prior to and throughout a war”, and although just war theory is a useful tool for this purpose, “it must be understood as only a crutch or partial palliative until the underlying pathologies can be understood, prevent ed and cured by more powerful 75 Ury, William. “A Global Immune System.” A ndover Bulletin Online Winter 2002: 95.2 Andover University. 22 February 2004 < http://www.liu.edu/cwis/cwp/library/workshop/citmla.htm >

PAGE 49

45 medicine.”76 What these voices bring to femi nist just peace is a commitment to the use of strong principles before the initiation of host ilities. Most importantly, just war theory’s principle of “last reso rt” can be resuscitated and placed within a visible and active just peace framework. Ury’s concept of just peace is no t new to women, who have long played these “third-sider” roles within their so cieties. According to anti-militarist feminists (standpoint feminists among them), the problem lies in the fact that the contributions of women and other ma rginalized groups remain largely unrecognized at institutional and policy le vels. However, because of this limited access to traditional avenues of power in decision making roles within governments and institutions, women hav e focused on grass roots organizing and non-governmental organizations as a means to power, managing to express their interests and concerns and placing femi nist issues on national, regional and international arenas. The Women and Armed Conflict List Archives77 provide a fascinating array of examples of such gr ass-root efforts from around the world. The views expressed in this archive “i ndicate that women and their organizations make use of innovative strategies for peace negotiation, peacemaking and peacebuilding….their main strategies s uggest not only alternative means of 76 Crawford, Neta. “Just War Theory and the U.S. Co unterterror War.” Harvard School of Public Health. 9 Apr 2004 http://www.hsph.harvard.edu/massviolence/r eadings/Just_War_Theory_&_Counterte.pdf 77 Women and Armed Conflict List Archives, Wo menWatch, United Namtions, October 1999Februaty 2000. < http://www.sdnp.undp.org/ww/women-armdconf/thrd2.html >

PAGE 50

46 doing politics and peacemaking, but also alternate understandings of politics and peacemaking.”78 One cooperative effort to raise women’ s’ public visibility and effect change is Women Waging Peace a website launched in 1999 at Harvard’s Kennedy School of Government which creates a net work of women in multiple conflict areas around the world who are “all dem onstrated leaders among women peace builders, are elected and appointed gover nment officials; directors of nongovernmental organizations (NGOs); lawyer s, scholars, and educators; business, military, and religious leader s; representatives of mu ltilateral organizations; and journalists.”79 This project allows peacemakers with a variety of skills and experiences to interact with each other, stud ying the work that they do in diverse conflict situations and roles and advocating the inclusion of women in local and international efforts to prevent, m anage and resolve conflicts. Another avenue was made possible by The International Women's Conference in Beijing, China which played a large role in the creation of the International Criminal Court; the passing of UN Security Council Resoluti on 1325 on issues of women, security and peace on October 31, 2000; and peacekeepi ng in the Democratic Republic of the Congo and in East Timor.80 The concerted effort of the transnational Women’s Caucus for Gender Justice succ eeded in their relentless determination 78 Bates, Prue. “Women and Peacemaking.” Development Bulletin, November 2000: 77. 79 Women Waging Peace. About Us. 22 February 2004. < http://www.w omenwagingpeace.net/ content/aboutus.asp > 80 Stiehm, Judith. “Recent Efforts by Femi nists to Advance Peace: Some Reports.” Signs 28.4 (2003): 1231-2.

PAGE 51

47 to bring charges of rape and sexual enslave ment, issues traditionally relegated to the private sphere, against three Serbian men in the International Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugos lavia, an important milestone in the fight to bring recognition to these crimes as forms of violence and subjugation. 81 An illustration of the power of witne ssing and narrating truth is the Densh Project, a digital archive of videotaped interviews, historic photographs and documents narrated by Japanese women and m en of the Pacific Northwest that balances the “dominant narratives of r egional history that minimize women’s experiences and foreground ‘‘heroic’ ’ actions of white males.”82 In one narrative, peace activist Aki Kuro se states, “Always realize that not to get involved when you should get involved is an act of violence.” 83 Hannah Arendt defines power as the opposite of violence, stating that “where the one rules absolutely, the other is absent.”84 True power resides, moreover “where words are not empty and deeds are not brutal, where words are not used to veil intentions but to discl ose realities, and deeds are not used to violate and destroy but to establish relations and create new realities.”85 81 Cooper, Sandi E. Peace as a Human Right: The Invasion of Women into the World of High International Politics. Journal of Women’s History 14.2 (2002): 10. 82 Nomura, Gail M. “Peace Empowers.” Frontiers: A Journal of Women Studies 22.3 (2001): 76. 83 Nomura, 89. 84 Arendt, Hannah. On Violence. San Diego, Ne w York & London: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1969: 56. 85 Arendt, Hannah. The Human Condition. Chicago & London: University of Chicago Press, 1958: 200.

PAGE 52

48 This definition is the cornerstone of women’s ways to just peace: acting cooperatively to effect change within existing systems and create new systems, witnessing and narrating their stories to re veal truth, and working to achieve equality for all marginalized groups by creating just and sustainable forms of economic development.

PAGE 53

49 Conclusion Just war theory is a reactive doctrine c onsisting of a set of guidelines that are meant to prevent unjust wars on a case by case basis. Unfortunately, as can be seen by its long history, it has had to undergo periodic adjustments to address evolving cultural and social system s and methods of war not previously imagined. The theory is now facing its deepest challenges, with a militarized world system that is armed to the teeth with ever more sophisticated and lethal weapons. Moreover, as can be seen with Wa lzer’s justification of means that would be unjust in normal circumstances political and military actors have moved away from the principles justifying entry into war to t hose that govern the process of war. The world is rapidly evol ving from a system of states as primary actors to one that includes an interrelated assortment of local, regional, and nongovernmental participant s. At the same time that modern wars are fought with increasing savagery and destructiveness, just war theorists have primarily moved from philosophical to procedural ru les about going to war, emphasizing international law, which is known to “c onfirm much more power than it denies.”86 Just peace, on the other hand, works wit hin any human system because it has always regarded conflict from a holistic per spective, as something that exists in all levels and arenas of human existence. Feminists reject the dichotomized rhetoric inherent in current discussions of war that refuses to acknowledge the interrelationship between domestic, national and international violence. Just war 86 Rengger, 358.

PAGE 54

50 theory perpetuates dichotomized views of war because it does not define war as something that exists within the system t hat perpetuates the cult ure of violence. Rather, it looks at each war as a specific event, analyzing each on a case by case basis. This is a reactive theor y that cannot deal with the underlying problems inherent in the su rrounding system that are the causes of conflict. This paper has shown that just peace is an active theory that promotes practices leading to the reduction of violenc e in all arenas and at all levels, from fights in the schoolyard to ethnic conflicts and beyond. It affirms the interrelationship between violence and the m ilitarism prevalent in current society and provides principles that can be used by people who are in traditional roles of authority as well as those in non-tr aditional grassroots, community or organizational levels and in all situations where violence exists. Just war theory can certainly continue to play a role but should be one tool within the larger framework of just peace theory.

PAGE 55

51 References Adenay, Bernard T. Just War, Political Realism, and Faith Metuchen, N.J. & London: The American Theological Li brary Association, 1988. Allen, Beverly.. Rape Warfare: The Hidden Genoci de in Bosnia-Herzegovina and Croatia. Minneapolis and London: University of Minnesota Press, 1996. Aquinas, Thomas. Summa Theologica First Part of the Se cond Part, Q. 90, trans. Fathers of the English Do minican Province, (Benziger Bros. Edition, 1947). 15 June 2002. < http://www.ccel.org/a/aquinas/ summa/FS/FS090.html#FSQ90OUTP1 > Arendt, Hannah. The Human Condition Chicago & London: University of Chicago, 1958. Arendt, Hannah. On Violence. San Diego, New York & London: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1969. Aristotle. The Politics and The Constitution of Athens trans. Jonathan Barnes, ed. Stephen Everson Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996. Berkham, Joyce.. “Feminism, War and Peace Polit ics: The Case of World War I.” Eds. Elshtain, J.B. and S. Tobias.. Women, Militarism & War: Essays in History, Politics, and Social Theory Maryland: Rowman and Littlefield Publishers, Inc., 1990. Cicero, Marcus Tullius. De Officiis, trans Walter Miller. Loeb Edition. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1913, B ook I.34. The Stoic Legacy to the Renaissance. 5 January 2002. < http://www.stoics.com/ > Chernus, Ira. 2002. General Eisenhower: Ideology and Discourse. East Lansing: Michigan State University Press. Cohn, Carol & Sara Ruddick. “A Feminist Ethical Perspective on Weapons of Mass Destruction.” to be published in Ethics and Weapons of Mass Destruction Eds. Steven Lee and Sohail Hashmi, under review at Cambridge University Press. 14 February 2004. < http://www.ksg.harvard.edu/wappp/ research/working/cohn_ruddick.pdf > Cooper, Sandi E. “Peace as a Human Right: T he Invasion of Women into the World of High International Politics.” Journal of Women’s History 14.2 (2002): 9-25.

PAGE 56

52 Cuomo, Chris. “War is Not Just An Event: Reflections on the Significance of Everyday Violence.” Hypatia 11.4 (1996): < http://gw.softlineweb.com. proxy.usf.edu/record.asp?m sel_from=0&msel_to=9&p review=&move=&returnPage=list.asp&articleID=114302&recNum=1 Dawson, Doyne. The Origins of Western Warfare Boulder, Colorado: Westview Press, 1996. Eichenberg, R.C. “Gender Diffe rences in Public Attitudes toward the Use of Force by the United States, 1990-2003”. International Security 28.1 (2003):110-41. Ehrenreich, Barbara. 2003. “The Roots of War.” The Progressive 67(4): 14. Elshtain, Jean Bethke. Women and War Chicago and London: The University of Chicago Press, 1987. Elshtain, Jean Bethke. Just War Theory Washington Square, New York: New York University Press. 1992. Elshtain, Jean Bethke. “Just War and Humanitarian Intervention .” Ideas 8.2 (2002): 4. Elshtain, Jean Bethke. “Luther’s Lamb: When and How to Fight a Just War.” Common Knowledge 8.2 (2002): 304-309. Goldstein, Joshua. 2001. How Gender Shapes the War System and Vice Versa Cambridge: Cambridge University Pr ess. War and Gender. Ed. Joshua Goldstein. 16 March 2003 < http://www.warandgender.com/ > Hutchings, Kimberly. “Ethics, Feminism, and In ternational Affairs.” Eds. Coicaud, JeanMarc and Daniel Warner. Ethics and International Affairs. New York: United Nations University Press, 2001. Kuhse, Helga. Caring: Nurses, Women and Ethics. Maldon, MA: Blackwell, 1997. LaCroix, W.L. War and International Ethics: Tradition and Today Lanham, New York & London: University Press of America, 1988. Luard, Evan. Basic Texts in International Relations New York: St. Martin’s Press, 1992 Meilaender, Gilbert. 2000. Michael Wa lzer: Just and Unjust Wars (1977). First Things 101 (2000):52-53. 9 March 2003. < http://www.firstthings.com/ftiss ues/ft0003/articles/ walzer.html >

PAGE 57

53 Mosely, Alex. “Just War Theory”, The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy 2001 15 June 2002. < http://www.utm.edu/ res earch/iep/j/justwar.htm > Nomura, Gail M. “Peace Empowers.” Frontiers: A Journal of Women Studies 22.3 (2001): 75-92 Nuremberg Trial Proceedings Vol 1 Avalon Project. Yale Law School. 9 March 2003. < http://www.yale.edu/lawweb /a valon/imt/proc/discrep.htm > Orend, Brian. War and International Justic e: A Kantian Perspective Waterloo & Ontario, Canada: Wilfrid Laurier Un iversity Press, 2000. Peach, Lucinda. “An Alternative to Pacifi sm? Feminism and Just-War Theory,” 1994. Bringing Peace Home.: Feminism, Violenc e and Nature. Eds. K.J. Warren and D.L. Cady. Bloomingt on and Indianapolis: Indiana Un iversity Press, 1996. Peters, Cynthia. “Women’s Patriotic Role,” ZNET (2001). 23 March 2003. < https://www.zmag.org > Rabrenovic, Gordana and Laura Rosko s. “Introduction: Civil So ciety, Feminism, and the Gendered Politics of War and Peace.” National Women’s Studies Association Journal 13.2 (2001):40-54. Rengger, Nicholas. “On The Just War Tradi tion In The Twenty-First Century.” International Affairs 78.2 (2002): 353-363. Roosevelt, Grace. “A Brief History of the Quest for Peace: Pacifism and Just War Theory in Europe from the 16th to the 20th Centuries.” Global Policy Forum. 23 June 2003. < http://www.globalpolicy.or g/resource/unhist/jinx1.htm > Roper, Lynne. 2001. “Feminism is NOT Pacifi sm: A Personal View of the Politics of War.” Feminist Media Studies, 2(1): 150-51. Stiehm, Judith. “Recent Efforts by Femini sts to Advance Peace: Some Reports.” Signs 28.4 (2003): 1231-2. Sylvester, Christine. “Feminist Theory and Gender Studies in International Relations”, International Studies Notes, 16/17, ( Fall 1991/Winter 1992 ) 3/1:32-38 Feminist Theory and Gender Studies. Internati onal Studies Association. 23 June 2002. < http://csf.colorado.edu/ isa/ftgs/index.html > Tong, Rosemarie, "Feminist Ethics", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2002 Edition) Edward N. Zalta (ed.), 23 March 2003. < http://plato.stanford.edu/archives / fall2002/entries/feminism-ethics />

PAGE 58

54 True, Jacqui. “Feminism.” Theories of International Relations, Eds. S. Burchill and A. Linklater, New York: St. Martin’s Press, 1995, 1996. Walker, R.B.J. "Gender and Crit ique in the Theory of International Relations" Ed. V. Spike Peterson Gendered States: Feminist (R e)Visions of International Relations Theory Boulder: Lyn ne Rienner, 1992. 179-202. Ury, William L. The Third Side: Why We Fight and How We Can Stop New York: Penguin Books, 2000. Ury, William. Must We Fight? From the Battlefield to the Schoolyard-A New Perspective on Violent Conflict & Its Prevention New York: John Wiley & Sons, 2001. Ury, William. “A Gl obal Immune System.” Andover Bulletin Online Winter 2002: 95.2 Andover University. 22 February 2004 < http://www.liu.edu/cwis/cwp/library/workshop/citmla.htm > Walzer, Michael. Just and Unjust Wars: A Moral Argum ent with Historical Illustrations Second edition, New York: Basi c Books, 1992.1 Walzer.,61–2. Women Waging Peace. About Us. 22 February 2004. < http://www.womenwagingpeace.net/ content/aboutus.asp > Zinn, Howard. 2002. “The Others.” The Nation 19 March 2003. < http://www.thenation.com/ doc.mhtml?i=20020211&s=zinn >

PAGE 59

55 Appendix A: Just Peacemaking: Te n Practices for Abolishing War (Pilgrim Press: August, 1998) Summary of the theory for the panel on Just Peacemaking Theory at the annual meeting of the Am erican Academy of Religion Orlando, Florida, November, 1998 Part One: PEACEMA KING INITIATIVES 1. Support nonviolent direct action. Nonviolent Direct Action is spreading widely, ending dictatorship in the Philippines, ending rule by the Shah in Iran, bringing about nonviolent revolutions in Poland, East Germany, and Central Europe, transforming injustice into democratic change in human rights moveme nts in Guatemala, Argentina, and elsewhere in Latin America, in South Af rica.... Governments and people have the obligation to make room for and to support nonviolent direct action. 2. Take independent initiatives to reduce threat. Independent initiatives: 1) are independent of the slow pr ocess of negotiation; 2) decrease threat perception and distrust but do not leave the initiator weak; 3) are verifiable actions; 4) and carried out at the announced time regardless of the other side's bluster; 5) have their purpos e clearly announced--to shift toward deescalation and to invite reciprocation; 6) come in a series; initiatives should continue in order to keep inviting re ciprocation. This new practice has been crucial in several recent breakthroughs. 3. Use cooperative conflict resolution. 1) Active partnership in developing solu tions, not merely passive cooperation. 2) Adversaries listen to each other and expe rience each others' perspectives, including culture, spiritua lity, story, history and emotion. 3) Seek longterm solutions which help prevent future conflic t. 4) Seek justice as a core component for sustainable peace. 4. Acknowledge responsibility for conflic t and injustice and seek repentance and forgiveness.

PAGE 60

56 Abstract A (continued) Until recently, it was widely agreed t hat nations would not express regret, acknowledge responsibility, or give fo rgiveness. But Germany since World War II, Japan and Korea, Clinton in Africa, the U.S. finally toward JapaneseAmericans during World War II, the S outh African Truth and Reconciliation Commission, and other actions described by Shriver, An Ethic for Enemies and Wink, When Powers Fall show a crucial new practice is emerging that can heal longstanding bitternesses. Part Two: JUSTICE 5. Advance democracy, human ri ghts, and religious liberty. Extensive empirical evidence shows that the spreading of democracy and respect for human rights, including relig ious liberty, is widening the zones of peace. Democracies fought no wars against one another during the entire twentieth century. They had fewer civil wars. And they generally devoted lower shares of their national products to military expenditures which decreases threats to other countries. Ties of economic interdependence by trade and investment also decrease the incidence of war. Engagem ent in international or ganizations like the UN and regional institutions is a clear predictive factor that they will be much less likely to engage in war. 6. Foster just and sustainable economic development. Sustainable development occurs wher e the needs of today are met without threatening the needs of tomorrow--w here those who lack adequate material and economic resources gain access, and those who have learn to control resource use and prevent future exhaustion. A key to economic development in East Asian countries, especially Korea and Taiwan, has been land reform that made w ealth more equitable and thus created a sizable local market for developing firms By contrast, Latin America lacks real land reform and equality, and therefore lo cal consumers cannot afford to buy products produced by local industries. Part Three: LOVE AND COMMUNITY 7. Work with emerging cooperative fo rces in the international system. Four trends have so altered the condi tions and practices of international

PAGE 61

57 Abstract A (continued) relations as to make it possible now, w here it was not possible before, to form and sustain voluntary associations for peace and other valuable common purposes that are in fact working: the decli ne in the utility of wa r; the priority of trade and the economy over war; the str ength of international exchanges, communications, transactions, and net works; and the gradual ascendancy of liberal representative democracy and a mixtur e of welfare-state and laissez-faire market economy. We should act so as to strengthen these trends and the international associations that they make possible. 8. Strengthen the United Na tions and international effo rts for cooperation and human rights. Acting alone, states cannot solve probl ems of trade, debt, in terest rates; of pollution, ozone depletion, acid rain, deplet ion of fish stocks, global warming; of migrations and refugees seeking asylum; of military security when weapons rapidly penetrate borders. Therefore, collective action is increasingly necessary. U.S. citizens should press their government to pay its UN dues and to act in ways that strengthen the effectiveness of the United Nations, of regional organizations, and of multilateral peacemaking, peacekeeping, and peace build ing. They resolve conflicts, monitor, nurture, and even enforce truc es. They meet human needs for food, hygiene, medicine, educati on, and economic interaction. Most wars now happen within states, not between states; ther efore, collective action needs to include UN-approved humanitarian intervention in cases like the former Yugoslavia, Haiti, Somalia, and Rwanda "when a stat e's condition or behavior results in... grave and massive violations of human rights." 9. Reduce offensive w eapons and weapons trade. A key factor in the decrease of war between nations is that weapons have become so destructive that war is not worth the price. Reducing offensive weapons and shifting toward defensive fo rce structures strengthens that equation. Banning chemical and biologic al weapons, and reducing strategic (long-range) nuclear warheads from 3, 500 to 1,000 each, are key steps. Arms imports by developing nations in 1995 dropped to one-quarter of their peak in 1988. But the power of money invested by arms manufacturers in politicians' campaigns is a major obstacle to reductions. 10. Encourage grassroots peacemaking groups and voluntary associations.

PAGE 62

58 Abstract A (continued) The existence of a growing worldwide people's movement constitutes one more historical force that makes just pe acemaking theory possible. They learn peacemaking practices and press government s to employ these practices; governments should protect such associat ions in law, and give them accurate information. Each practice is recent in its widespr ead use, and is causing significant change. Together they exert strong influence, decreasing wars. Each is empirically happening and being effective in abolishing some wars. Each faces significant obstacles and blocking forces that are named in the chapters. We contend that just peacemaking practices are ethica lly obligatory for persons, groups, and governments to strengt hen them and help overcome the blocking forces.