USF Libraries
USF Digital Collections

Experience and inquiry in John Dewey's contextualism

MISSING IMAGE

Material Information

Title:
Experience and inquiry in John Dewey's contextualism
Physical Description:
Book
Language:
English
Creator:
Kirby, Christopher C
Publisher:
University of South Florida
Place of Publication:
Tampa, Fla.
Publication Date:

Subjects

Subjects / Keywords:
Pragmatism
Logic
Metaphysics
Epistemology
Empiricism
Dissertations, Academic -- Philosophy -- Masters -- USF   ( lcsh )
Genre:
government publication (state, provincial, terriorial, dependent)   ( marcgt )
bibliography   ( marcgt )
theses   ( marcgt )
non-fiction   ( marcgt )

Notes

Abstract:
ABSTRACT: This paper will focus on two elements, viz. experience and inquiry, which are central to John Deweys philosophy and their relation to the movement known as pragmatism. Although each of these concepts has received extensive treatment by other schools of thought, the pragmatists, and particularly Dewey, did much to redefine each in hopes of alleviating the tension between conflicting philosophical viewpoints. An explication of Deweys view on experience is the first step in understanding his application of the pragmatic method towards reconstructing philosophical thinking. Therefore, this paper will explore the meaning that Dewey gave to each and how that meaning is helpful to the overall pragmatist project of reuniting philosophical speculation with practical consequences.
Thesis:
Thesis (M.A.)--University of South Florida, 2005.
Bibliography:
Includes bibliographical references.
System Details:
System requirements: World Wide Web browser and PDF reader.
System Details:
Mode of access: World Wide Web.
Statement of Responsibility:
by Christopher C. Kirby.
General Note:
Title from PDF of title page.
General Note:
Document formatted into pages; contains 74 pages.

Record Information

Source Institution:
University of South Florida Library
Holding Location:
University of South Florida
Rights Management:
All applicable rights reserved by the source institution and holding location.
Resource Identifier:
aleph - 001670355
oclc - 62294055
usfldc doi - E14-SFE0001219
usfldc handle - e14.1219
System ID:
SFS0025540:00001


This item is only available as the following downloads:


Full Text
xml version 1.0 encoding UTF-8 standalone no
record xmlns http:www.loc.govMARC21slim xmlns:xsi http:www.w3.org2001XMLSchema-instance xsi:schemaLocation http:www.loc.govstandardsmarcxmlschemaMARC21slim.xsd
leader nam Ka
controlfield tag 001 001670355
003 fts
005 20051216093314.0
006 m||||e|||d||||||||
007 cr mnu|||uuuuu
008 051117s2005 flu sbm s000 0 eng d
datafield ind1 8 ind2 024
subfield code a E14-SFE0001219
035
(OCoLC)62294055
SFE0001219
040
FHM
c FHM
049
FHMM
090
B72 (Online)
1 100
Kirby, Christopher C.
0 245
Experience and inquiry in John Dewey's contextualism
h [electronic resource] /
by Christopher C. Kirby.
260
[Tampa, Fla.] :
b University of South Florida,
2005.
502
Thesis (M.A.)--University of South Florida, 2005.
504
Includes bibliographical references.
516
Text (Electronic thesis) in PDF format.
538
System requirements: World Wide Web browser and PDF reader.
Mode of access: World Wide Web.
500
Title from PDF of title page.
Document formatted into pages; contains 74 pages.
3 520
ABSTRACT: This paper will focus on two elements, viz. experience and inquiry, which are central to John Deweys philosophy and their relation to the movement known as pragmatism. Although each of these concepts has received extensive treatment by other schools of thought, the pragmatists, and particularly Dewey, did much to redefine each in hopes of alleviating the tension between conflicting philosophical viewpoints. An explication of Deweys view on experience is the first step in understanding his application of the pragmatic method towards reconstructing philosophical thinking. Therefore, this paper will explore the meaning that Dewey gave to each and how that meaning is helpful to the overall pragmatist project of reuniting philosophical speculation with practical consequences.
590
Adviser: John P. Anton.
653
Pragmatism.
Logic.
Metaphysics.
Epistemology.
Empiricism.
690
Dissertations, Academic
z USF
x Philosophy
Masters.
773
t USF Electronic Theses and Dissertations.
4 856
u http://digital.lib.usf.edu/?e14.1219



PAGE 1

Experience and Inquiry in John Deweys Contextualism by Christopher C. Kirby A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts Department of Philosophy College of Arts and Sciences University of South Florida Major Professor: John P. Anton, Ph.D. Charles Guignon, Ph.D. Michael Gibbons, Ph.D. Date of Approval: April 8, 2005 Keywords: Pragmatism, Logic, Metaphysics, Epistemology, Empiricism Copyright 2005 Christopher C. Kirby

PAGE 2

i TABLE OF CONTENTS List of Abbreviations ....................................................................................................ii Abstract ........................................................................................................................iii Preface The Method of Pragmatism ..........................................................................1 A Method, Not a Theory ..................................................................................1 The Development of Pragmatic Method in John Deweys Work ....................3 Chapter One Experience: The Formation of Context ................................................8 The Subject-Matter of Philosophy ................................................................8 Developing a Naturalistic Account ................................................................11 Mapping Out Experience ................................................................................19 Experience and Context ..................................................................................29 Chapter Two Inquiry: The Enrichment of Context .................................................33 The Search for a Pattern .................................................................................33 The Indeterminate Situation as Impoverished Context ..................................39 The Pattern Of Inquiry ....................................................................................42 The Determinate Situation as Enriched Context ............................................47 Chapter Three Growth: The Outcome of Context and the Pragmatic Method ........51 The Importance of Habit ................................................................................51 Forming Habits Through Inquiry ...................................................................56 Habit Reconstruction and Growth ..................................................................62 Pragmatic Method and Context ......................................................................66 References ..................................................................................................................69 Bibliography ...............................................................................................................70

PAGE 3

ii L IST OF ABBREVIATIONS Works by John Dewey: Southern Illinois University Press publishes a collection of John Deweys complete works in 37 volumes. They are separated into three sections: The Early Works The Middle Works and The Later Works. My citations will follow the standard format of referencing the section, volume and page number in this collection, save for when the citation also can be found in a separately published volume. Then, I will include the following abbreviations. HWT How We Think (1910)(Rev. 1933) (MW 6) DE Democracy and Education (1916) (MW 9) RP Reconstruction in Philosophy (1920) (MW 12) HNC Human Nature and Conduct (1922) (MW 14) EN Experience and Nature (1925) (LW 1) PP The Public and its Problems (1927) (LW 2) QC The Quest for Certainty (1929) (LW 4) ION Individualism: Old and New (1930) (LW 5) CF A Common Faith (1934) (LW 9) AE Art as Experience (1934) (LW 10) LSA Liberalism and Social Action (1935) (LW 11) LTI Logic: The Theory of Inquiry (1938) (LW 12) EE Experience and Education (1939) (LW 13) FC Freedom and Culture (1939) (LW 13)

PAGE 4

iii EXPERIENCE AND INQUIRY IN JOHN DEWEYS CONTEXTUALISM Christopher C. Kirby ABSTRACT This paper will focus on two elements, viz experience and inquiry, which are central to John Deweys philosophy and their relation to the movement known as pragmatism. Although each of these concepts has received extensive treatment by other schools of thought, the pragmatists, and particularly Dewey, did much to redefine each in hopes of alleviating the tension between conflicting philosophical viewpoints. An explication of Deweys view on experience is the first step in understanding his application of the pragmatic method towards reconstructing philosophical thinking. Therefore, this paper will explore the meaning that Dewey gave to each and how that meaning is helpful to the overall pragmatist project of reuniting philosophical speculation with practical consequences.

PAGE 5

PREFACE THE METHOD OF PRAGMATISM Philosophy recovers itself when it ceases to be a device for dealing with the problems of philosophers and becomes a method, cultivated by philosophers, for dealing with the problems of men. [MW 10:46] A Method, Not a Theory Todays world is one of great uncertainty. We are faced with problems both old and new, and on a larger scale than our species has ever before witnessed. It could be said that the tools of philosophy, i.e. its theories and abstractions, were first forged by humanitys quest for safety against the uncertainty of life. But, if philosophy hopes to successfully address the problems facing it now, it may be forced to return from its theoretical abstractions to concrete life. The American philosophical movement that thrived between the Civil War and World War II, commonly known as pragmatism, was founded on this notion. Unfortunately, pragmatism has been mischaracterized by much of the philosophic community. And, although it is fairly well recognized that one of the main precepts of pragmatism is the call for philosophic endeavors to concern themselves with concrete problems rather than abstract speculations, there is nevertheless a public misunderstanding over the meaning of pragmatism. While past philosophers have made similar claims about practicality, pragmatism is set apart by the gravity it placed on the notion. This has led to an unfortunate caricature of pragmatism as the philosophical endorsement of 1

PAGE 6

opportunism, found in the worst parts of American industry and commerce. Yet, this is a point that nearly every thinker in the pragmatic tradition has explicitly denied. 1 Even those who have some familiarity with pragmatism have tended to misjudge its most central tenets. 2 One of the most notable misunderstandings is perhaps the equation of pragmatism with what has been called the pragmatic theory of truth. The upshot of this confusion is the identification of the platitude Truth is what works as pragmatisms major (and perhaps only) contribution to philosophy. However, such a depiction captures what many pragmatists would claim is perhaps only a consequence of pragmatism and not one of its central tenets. For instance, Charles Sanders Peirce, who coined the movements name, saw pragmatism as primarily a criterion for determining the meaning of words. Only through the work of his friend and colleague, William James, was a more general conception of pragmatism as a theory about truth offered. Yet, even James as the subtitle of his 1907 work Pragmatism reveals preferred to see pragmatism as A New Name for Some Old Ways of Thinking. As he put it elsewhere, Philosophies, whether expressed in sonnets or systems, all must wear this form. The thinker starts from some experience of the practical world, and asks its meaning. He launches himself upon the speculative sea, and makes a voyage long or short. He ascends into the empyrean, and communes with the eternal essences. But whatever his achievements and discoveries be while gone, the utmost result they can issue in is some new practical maxim or 1 For example, consider James remark to H.G. Wells, the moral flabbiness born of the exclusive worship of the bitch-goddess SUCCESS. Thatwith the squalid cash interpretation put on the word successis our national disease. The Letters of William James, vol. 2 (1920). And, John Deweys assertion Pragmatism is far from being that glorification of action for its own sake which is regarded as the peculiar characteristic of American life. (LW 2:5) 2 Bertrand Russells indictment of Deweys notion of inquiry is arguably one instance of this. (cf. Deweys New Logic, In The Library of Living Philosophers, vol. 1. ed. By Paul Schilpp and Lewis Hahn. Lasalle, IL: Open Court, (3 rd edition) 1989. 2

PAGE 7

resolve, or the denial of some old one, with which inevitably he is sooner or later washed ashore on the terra firma of concrete life again. 3 As James so poetically expresses in this passage, the main principle of pragmatism finding the difference an idea makes to the real world underlies all philosophical inquiry. With this in mind, pragmatism ought to be seen not as North Americas attempt to replace old theories with new ones, but rather as an overhauling of the method of philosophical thinking through a coalescing of abstract reason with practical consequence. In this spirit, James, citing the Italian novelist Giovanni Papini, claimed that pragmatism lies in the midst of [all] our theories, like a corridor in a hotel. Innumerable chambers open out of it. 4 The Development of Pragmatic Method in John Deweys Work To attempt to address the above-mentioned mischaracterization as it applies to the entire tradition of pragmatism would present too large of a task to accomplish in this investigation. Therefore, this paper will focus mainly only on the philosophy of one of the pragmatic thinkers. And, although Peirce and James are pivotal figures in the development of pragmatism, their views differed to such an extent that to focus on either, in my opinion, would present only one pole of pragmatic thought. Fortunately, there was a figure that coalesced the differences of Peirce and James while staying true to their shared desire to give a method for dealing with the potency 3 James, William. Reflex Action and Theism, from The Will to Believe and Other Essays in Popular Philosophy. (Dover: 1956) pgs. 142-143 4 James, William. What Pragmatism Means. from Pragmatism and Other Writings. (New York: Penguin Classics) 2000. pg. 26 [my brackets] 3

PAGE 8

of ideas. This figure was John Dewey, Peirces one-time student at Johns Hopkins and an admirer and avid reader of James work. Born in 1859 to a Burlington grocer, Dewey has been considered by many to be the most prolific philosopher the United States has ever produced, though he may have rejected that title in favor of being remembered as an intellectual at large. For, on his view, it was the responsibility of the philosopher to be just as concerned with public issues as with esoteric ones. His work which included an array of publications related to politics, pedagogy, logic, and even art could be seen as the embodiment of this view. And, although Dewey preferred to call his philosophy instrumentalism, because of its emphasis on the utility of ideas in explicating how human beings relate to their surroundings, he arguably did more to promote and sustain the ideas of pragmatism than any other thinker of his time. 5 However, Dewey did not begin his career as a pragmatist. His mature position developed slowly over the course of his very lengthy career, which lasted for more than seventy years. His body of work is so prodigious that it has been divided into three periods early, middle and late roughly corresponding with what many consider the three major stages of his career the idealistic, experimental and naturalistic. 6 It was in the second stage of his career that Dewey began to assert, like 5 Although James is considered by many to be the foremost pragmatist, because he died at the relatively early age of 62, as compared to Deweys 93 years, and because Dewey traveled extensively, it could be said that Deweys influence reached a broader audience and for a longer period of time. There are many excellent biographical works on Dewey that illustrate the range of his influence. A good introduction for those unfamiliar with Deweys work would be Paul Stratherns Dewey in 90 Minutes. (Ivan R. Dee Press: Chicago, 2002.) 6 In his introduction to Deweys On Experience, Nature, and Freedom, Richard Bernstein identifies three distinct periods in Deweys thought, each lasting approximately twenty years. In Deweys Metaphysics. (New York: Fordham University Press, 1988) Raymond Boisvert labels the first of these 4

PAGE 9

Peirce before him, that the method employed by the natural sciences (one that placed theories on probation until some practical data could affirm or refute them) was the method that needed to be applied in philosophy. 7 In subsequent years, once Dewey had been exposed to James radical empiricism, i.e. the belief that experience as a whole is more than the sum of its parts, he would revise that assertion to include all experience, not merely the reflective experience of philosophical inquiry. The point of departure for this analysis will be the years just before Dewey penned Experience and Nature and thus completed his transition toward naturalism. It could be argued that his brand of naturalism consists in two basic criteria: that psychological states are reducible to terms about organisms interacting with their environment, and, that a form of inquiry patterned after science is the only way to utilize experience in dealing with the world. Taken together, these suggest that nature is a sort of context in which humankind finds itself embedded. It is my contention that the overarching theme of Deweys philosophy is, that the most pervasive fallacy of philosophic thinking goes back to neglect of context. 8 Although I believe that all of Deweys major works after his 1910 offering, How We Think (confer with the Abbreviations section above), address this theme to some extent or another, four titles in particular Human Nature and Conduct (1922), Experience and Nature (1925), Art as Experience (1934), and Logic: The Theory of Inquiry (1938) will periods Deweys Idealistic Years, which refers to the pivotal role of Kantian and Hegelian philosophy in this stage of Deweys development. 7 Cf. The Rules of Philosophy, from Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce. ed. by Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss. (Cambridge: Harvard University Press) 1934. pgs 156-158, in which Peirce wrote In sciences in which men come to agreement, when a theory has been broached it is considered to be on probation until this agreement is reached. 8 LW 6:5 5

PAGE 10

serve as my main focus. For it was in those four volumes that Dewey worked out the conceptual roots of his mature thought referred to as contextualism. While the notion of context was of the utmost importance to Deweys thought, oddly enough, he rarely wrote on the topic explicitly. This has lent some vagueness to this aspect of his thought and is typically treated by Dewey scholars with obscurity, if treated at all. That is a tendency I wish to avoid in this analysis, but since I will treat Deweys notion of context in extensa in the following chapters it will suffice in this preface to define contextualism as a philosophical emphasis on the environmental, historical and cultural frameworks of ideas. As I will contend, Deweys expression of the pragmatic method, in which he employed both Peircean and Jamesean elements, can be properly understood only when its backward-looking, contextual and forward-looking, instrumental components are understood. In this analysis, I will recount the core concepts that constitute Deweys version of the pragmatic method, viz. experience and inquiry, and analyze how they exemplify the union of his contextualism and instrumentalism. To sum up my goal in one sentence, I believe that Deweys work demonstrates that pragmatic method is the recognition of context. In chapter one, Experience: The Formation of Context I will explore the features of Deweys conception of experience that set it apart from other accounts as well as discuss the implications this account has for Deweys conception of context. My second chapter, Inquiry: The Enrichment of Context, will focus on Deweys view of inquiry, which could be called the central mechanism of his entire corpus (with his 1938 publication Logic: The Theory of Inquiry being the most 6

PAGE 11

complete articulation of the concept.) I will examine the role inquiry plays, according to Dewey, in the formation of contexts. Growth: The Outcome of Context and the Pragmatic Method, my third chapter, will address the implications and byproducts of Deweys rendering of experience and inquiry by explicating Deweys term growth as it is expressed in what he called habit reconstruction. There, I will also address the anticipated tensions that might surround my reading of these conceptions as Deweys means for reconstructing the method of philosophical investigation that he called, alternately, pragmatism and instrumentalism. 7

PAGE 12

CHAPTER ONE EXPERIENCE: THE FORMATION OF CONTEXT Reference to the primacy and ultimacy of the material of ordinary experience protects us from creating artificial problems which deflect the energy and attention of philosophers from the real problems that arise out of actual subject-matter. [EN, LW 1:26] The Subject-Matter of Philosophy Dewey was not the first philosopher to stress the importance of experience to philosophical study; neither was he first pragmatist to do so. In fact, both Peirce and James believed experience played a vital role in the application of the pragmatic method. In The Development of American Pragmatism, Dewey attributed the origin of pragmatism to a passage in Kants Metaphysics of Morals, happened upon by Peirce, wherein, Kant established a distinction between pragmatic and practical. The latter term applies to moral laws which Kant regards as a priori, whereas the former term applies to the rules of art and technique which are based on experience and are applicable to experience. 9 In a collection of his lectures, published under the title Pragmatism (1907), William James acknowledged the Kantian roots of pragmatism, but also pointed to the etymology of the word one he attributed to ancient Greece in order to show that pragmatism harmonizes with many ancient philosophic tendencies. 10 He hoped to 9 LW 2:3 10 James, William. What Pragmatism Means. from Pragmatism and Other Writings. (New York: Penguin Classics) 2000. pg. 28 As James put it elsewhere, There is absolutely nothing new in the pragmatic method. Socrates was an adept at it. Aristotle used it methodically. Locke, Berkeley, and Hume made momentous contributions to truth by its means. pg. 27 8

PAGE 13

identify philosophical investigation, as such, with the empiricist attitude that unstiffens theories and sets inquiry at work within the stream of [ones] experience. 11 He dubbed his position radical empiricism and wrote that for those who would adopt it the crudity of experience remains an eternal element [of the world] thereof. There is no possible point of view from which the world can appear an absolutely single fact. 12 Any analysis of Deweys notion of experience must start from an explication of this position, for it was James sentiment that philosophical debates be reducible to terms about experience that was perhaps the single greatest influence on Deweys thought. James position might best be understood as the view that experience is something that we cannot go beyond, i.e. experience is all we have and there is nothing real outside of it. And, although James view of experience was now broader in scope than Peirce had originally seen it, it was based on a similar rejection of the Enlightenment view that saw experience as the locus of interaction between the objective world and the subjective perceiver a distinction Dewey also rejected. As he put it, What has been completely divided in philosophical discourse into man and world, inner and outer, self and not-self, subject and object, individual and social, private and public, etc. are actually parties in life-transactions. The philosophical problem of trying to get them back together is artificial. 13 He believed that experience and the problems that arise out of it are neither merely the beginning of knowledge, nor a useful tool for linking up mind with world, but rather, the entire subject-matter of philosophy. He hoped that he could save 11 Ibid. pg. 28 12 The Works of William James. Cambridge, MA and London: Harvard University Press, 17 vol., 1975 The Will to Believe, pg. 6 13 LW 16:248 9

PAGE 14

philosophy from itself by removing the various artifices of dualisms and, in this regard, his work on experience could be seen as a type of prolegomena to any future epistemology. Thus, what Dewey meant by the term experience differed significantly from the way many of his predecessors and contemporaries had used it, i.e. as the influx of sensory data. In several of his early essays, Dewey laid the foundation for the more robust interpretation of experience, exemplified by Experience and Nature (1925) and Art as Experience (1934), which he hoped would redeem the term by having it returned to its idiomatic usages. 14 But here, idiom is not tantamount to vulgarity or simplicity. Rather, Dewey sought a return to thinking about experience in less dissected, philosophically abstract terms. Terms that would avoid many of the conceptual eddies that had plagued philosophy for centuries. For him, the progress of philosophy had been stagnated by those eddies, and he hoped to reconstruct it by reminding us that philosophy must not be a study of philosophy, but a study, by means of philosophy, of life-experience and our beliefs about and in this experience. 15 Deweys project was aimed at this goal, and he sought to accomplish it by showing how experience is inextricably linked with context. By his lights, experience sets the stage for understanding context, i.e. a proper illustration of experience can 14 cf. LW 1:361-3 15 John J. Stuhr, John Dewey. in Pragmatism and Classical American Philosophy: Essential Readings and Interpretive Essays. Ed. John J. Stuhr (New York: Oxford University Press, 2000.) pg. 435 NOTE: Philosophy, as it appears in this sentence, refers to three separate human enterprises, each used by Dewey in a specific sense. The first refers to philosophy in its professional capacity; the second refers to the philosophical problems of history; and the third refers to the reconstructed endeavor that Dewey wanted to imbue with experimentalism. 10

PAGE 15

disclose or lay bare contextual frameworks. Of course, in order to demonstrate such a thesis, more clarification of 1) Deweys account of experience and 2) what he meant by the term context are needed. I am confident that once these concepts are clear, we will see that experience is best understood as the opening up, or engendering, of contextual transactions. However, first it may be helpful to recount some of the major movements in Deweys thought that led to the development of the first measure of his naturalism, i.e. the casting of psychological states in terms of the interaction between organisms and environments. Developing a Naturalistic Account Although Deweys account of experience could be characterized as a decisive break from previous outlooks, it did not arise in a vacuum. Throughout his lengthy career, Dewey came into contact with many different views, such as Darwinian naturalism, Kantian and Hegelian idealism, German romanticism, and perhaps most notably British empiricism. He tackled any new idea with enthusiasm, even in his later years, and was able to glean a great deal from each. But, the last twenty-five years of Deweys life, the period in which he most completely conveyed his version of pragmatism, hinged upon an empiricism that could be called naturalistic (though Dewey preferred the term instrumentalist) and which moved beyond any single influence, even beyond James radical empiricism. Briefly stated, Deweys naturalism hinges upon the notion that human beings can best be 11

PAGE 16

understood through their relationships with their surroundings. 16 The upshot of this naturalistic empiricism is the belief that thought and action are two parts of a single process and that mind and world name philosophical abstractions rather than existent entities. As he put it, The nature of experience is determined by the essential conditions of life. While man is other than bird and beast, he shares basic vital functions with them and has to make the same basal adjustments if he is to continue the process of living. 17 In what follows, I sketch some of the major developments in Deweys thinking towards this position. As an undergraduate at the University of Vermont, Dewey had been impressed with Kants philosophy. His earliest publication, The Metaphysical Assumptions of Materialism(1882), reflected the Kantian tendency to convert metaphysical problems to epistemological ones when he criticized materialists for being logically inconsistent, viz. that They claim to possess a certain kind of knowledge, but are unable to explain the derivation of that knowledge on a strictly materialistic basis. 18 However, Dewey soon came to move beyond this affinity for epistemologically grounded philosophy as he was introduced to Hegel as a graduate student at Johns Hopkins University. The time spent on Kant, though, was never fully forgotten, as became obvious in later writings where Dewey often returned to the notion of mediated knowledge. 16 Deweys brand of naturalism is a precursor to later versions, which argued for describing mental phenomenon in the terms of natural science, expounded by thinkers such as W.V.O. Quine and Donald Davidson. 17 AE, LW 10:19 18 Boisvert, Raymond. Deweys Metaphysics. New York: Fordham University Press, 1988. pg. 17 12

PAGE 17

The individual who had the greatest impact on Deweys thought as a graduate student at Johns Hopkins, and who helped him beyond Kant, was the neo-Hegelian scholar G.S. Morris. However, Morris brand of Hegelianism was unique in that it rejected the dialectic of Geist in favor of a more biological description of the dynamism of nature. In other words, the traditional subject in epistemology became redefined as an organism fully immersed in and interacting with a dynamic, organic environment i.e. one that incorporates the organism. This move, which was vital to Deweys later thought, came to Morris from his mentor Trendelenburg, who had been sharply influenced by Aristotles notion of potentiality-actuality and Darwins theory of evolution. Trendelenburg synthesized these two ideas into what he called constructive motion which he saw as the common trait between thought and being. On one hand, thought moves from potentiality to actuality, per Aristotle, as it becomes the object that is thought, on the other hand, being moves from potentiality to actuality, per Darwin, through natural selection. This reading renders the notion of telos a type of biological end in both nature and organisms. 19 Deweys teacher Morris, in turn, appropriated these ideas in his own work as he aimed at detailing the meaning of existence and the undermining of dualisms. Dewey later echoed the biologized Hegelianism of Trendelenberg and Morris in Experience and Nature, with passages such as, If we consider the form or scheme of the situation in which meaning and understanding occur, we find an involved simultaneous presence and cross-reference of immediacy and efficiency, overt actuality and potentiality, the consummatory and instrumental. 20 19 For a more detailed description of Trendelenburgs constructive motion see Boisvert, Raymond. Deweys Metaphysics. New York: Fordham University Press, 1988. pgs. 22-24 20 EN, LW 1:143 13

PAGE 18

During these early stages in his career, Deweys move from Kant to Hegel can best be characterized as a shift from epistemology to ontology. The difference is the way he dealt with the relationship between mind and world, viz. a shift from a dualistic view to a more holistic one. In 1903, Dewey published Studies in Logical Theory, which is commonly taken to be his definitive break from idealism toward experimentalism. However, the foundations for this volume were worked out gradually over the course of the preceding years as Dewey became less captivated by Hegelianism. The two largest contributing factors in Deweys empirical turn were his work at Johns Hopkins with the psychologist G. Stanley Hall, who showed him how scientific analysis could be applied to the humanities, and his later collaboration with J.H. Tufts at the University of Michigan. Dewey left Michigan to join Tufts at the University of Chicago and it was there that he developed a philosophical approach that coalesced pragmatism with his Darwinian leanings, viz. instrumentalism. Over the following ten years, Dewey flourished in this environment as he worked out the implications of combining Peirces pragmatism, James radical empiricism and Darwinian naturalism with a scientific approach. Briefly stated, the upshot of combining these three schools of thought was that while nature was in constant change, human beings could still act in their environment by testing their beliefs and adjusting them according to usefulness in experience. In other words, if human beings observe, through experimentation, what actions are best, then they will form "good laboratory habits." These habits share a normative feature with Kant's 14

PAGE 19

universal maxim, i.e. those that can be applied by all inquirers, are best. Moral imperatives, then, refer to some tried and tested method, not an ideal drawn from the blue. 21 Deweys work is unique insofar as it took these already established ideas, assimilated them with others, and built upon them an outlook that, when understood properly, coalesced the seemingly disparate functions of experience, inquiry, and learning. In this way, it could be argued, his mature view (exemplified by Experience and Nature and Art as Experience) aimed at giving insight into what it means to be human. Two early essays in particular laid the foundation for that more robust expression of experience. When the first of these essays, The Reflex Arc Concept in Psychology, appeared in 1896, it marked one of the truly important turning points in the study of human behavior. 22 There, Dewey attacked the mechanistic view of stimulus and response that dominated the psychological research of the period. On his view, the reflex arc concept only mimicked an older, and erroneous, mind-body dualism by placing stimulus in opposition to response. He wrote, we still incline to interpret the latter [i.e. response] from our preconceived and preformulated ideas of rigid distinctions between sensations, thoughts and acts. The sensory stimulus is one thing, the central activity, standing for the idea, is another thing, and the motor discharge, standing for the act proper, is a third. As a result, the reflex arc is not a comprehensive, or organic unity, but a 21 LTI, LW 12:108 22 cf. EW 5:XVIII [William McKenzies introduction the fifth volume of Deweys Early Works] where McKenzie continued with, It remained for decades one of the most influential works in the science of psychology and still retains that position among all students not dogmatically committed to some form, by whatever name, of the same mechanistic view that it attempts to correct. 15

PAGE 20

patchwork of disjointed parts, a mechanical conjunction of unallied processes. 23 In this regard, Dewey complained, the reflex arc was inaccurate because it placed the parts of an act prior to the whole. It failed to recognize that stimulus, movement, and response only made sense as an interpretation of an event after it had occurred. Moreover, he claimed, that the notions of stimulus and response were non-existent entities that only gain meaning once placed in relation to one another. Simply put, Dewey argued that the reflex arc was an instance of the empiricists fallacy of placing the parts prior to the whole. Dewey offered a more naturalistic account, one that viewed stimulus and response in less mechanistic terms, i.e. as parts of a single process. On such a view, the reflex arc does not run in a linear direction from stimulus, through response, to movement. Rather, multiple stimuli, responses, and movements arise simultaneously and are experienced, in chorus, as a singular, unbroken act, which is as experienced no more mere sensation than it is mere motion, and thus, when analysis dissects the reflex arc into separate states, we have, only the serial steps in a co-ordination of acts. 24 Simply put, before an act can be divided into parts, its quality as a whole has to be explicated. But, the reflex arc concept offered no such explanation. Toward the close of the 19 th century, as Dewey began to embrace pragmatism, he became enamored with James radical empiricism and began to formulate his own version, which, by 1905, he had dubbed immediate 23 EW 5:97 24 EW 5:106 16

PAGE 21

empiricism. 25 His essay, The Postulate of Immediate Empiricism, which appeared in July of that year, reveals James influence on his thinking. Therein, Deweys postulate was aimed at framing all philosophical debate in terms of experience, on the one hand, and eradicating the notion that experience needs to be grounded in a transcendent reality or a transcendental truth absolutely free from time and contingency, on the other. As he put it, things anything, everything, in the ordinary non-technical use of the term thing are what they are experienced as. 26 To illustrate this, Dewey described a situation where a person, sitting in a dark room, might hear a noise that frightens them. When the lights are turned on and the harmless source of the noise identified, rather than saying that the noise appeared frightful and was really harmless, Dewey suggested that we ought to identify the noise as truly frightful when first heard, and later because more information is available to apply to the gross experience it is truly harmless. Saying the latter would be more useful than positing, as someone who used the former explanation would, a distinction between appearances and reality. Dewey wanted to make it clear that the experienced noise was just what it was experienced as at that time, namely frightening. On this account, if one wishes to describe anything truly, his task is to tell what it is experienced as being. 27 Compare this with a passage from James The Meaning of Truth (1909): Radical empiricism consists first of a postulate that the only things debatable among philosophers shall be things definable in terms of experience. The generalized conclusion is that therefore 25 Although critical of some of its conclusions, Dewey had been particularly impressed with James The Will to Believe [1897], in which James first described his position as radical empiricism. 26 MW 3:158 27 MW 3:158 17

PAGE 22

the parts of experience hold together from next to next by relations that are themselves parts of experience. 28 This passage, on the one hand, illustrates the parallel between these two thinkers views. On the other hand, insofar as James had adopted Deweys reference to a postulate, it may suggest the admiration that Dewey felt for James was probably mutual. In any case, what is clear is that by the release of the The Postulate of Immediate Empiricism Deweys thought had come into its own. Another example that Dewey used in that article was Zllners illusion an optical illusion displaying lines that appear to be convergent, yet are truly parallel. Opponents of Deweys view might use this picture as an example of how describing something in terms of experiencing as does not do justice to the nature of the experienced object. To this Dewey responds, That experience is that two lines with certain cross-hatchings are apprehended as convergent; only by taking that experience as real and as fully real, is there any basis for or way of going to an experienced knowledge that the lines are parallel. It is in the concrete thing as experienced that all the grounds and clues to its own intellectual or logical rectification are contained. 29 The last sentence of this passage reveals that Dewey agreed with James that the generalized conclusion of this postulate was that [t]he directly apprehended universe 28 The Works of William James. Cambridge, MA and London: Harvard University Press, 17 vol., 1975. The Meaning of Truth, pp. 6-7 [emphasis added] 29 MW 3:163 18

PAGE 23

needs no extraneous transempirical connective support. 30 Thus, with the appearance of the Postulate paper Dewey had, once and for all, rejected the subjective, psychical view of experience and the subsequent division of knowing from the known that was prevalent in much of his early work. Elements of James view could still be found in Deweys work twenty years later when he wrote in the first chapter of his Experience and Nature, When objects are isolated from the experience through which they are reached and in which they function, experience itself becomes reduced to the mere process of experiencing, and experiencing is therefore treated as if it were also complete in itself. 31 Dewey warned against the enterprise of selective emphasis i.e. the tendency to emphasize the parts of experience that are clearest or most important. When philosophers are not mindful of this tendency they may end up positing intellectual abstractions as absolute being. This conversion of eventual functions into antecedent existence is what Dewey called the philosophic fallacy. 32 In order to avoid committing this fallacy in regard to experience itself, Dewey sought to map out only its generic traits. Doing this, he believed would render a coherent account without spinning off into abstractions. Mapping Out Experience For the last half of his life, Dewey aimed at reinstating a more natural, holistic view of experience that was rooted in the recognition of the interconnectedness of perceiver and surroundings. He believed this view of 30 The Works of William James Cambridge, MA and London: Harvard University Press, 17 vol., 1975. The Meaning of Truth, pg. 7 31 EN, LW 1:13 32 EN, LW 1:34 [Deweys emphasis] 19

PAGE 24

experience and the problems that arose out of avoiding this view were the subject matter of all philosophical study. Other [philosophic] methods begin with results of a reflection that has already torn in two the subject-matter experienced and the operations and states of experiencing. The problem then is to get together again what has been sundered which is as if the kings men started with the fragments of the egg and tried to construct the whole egg out of them. 33 By his lights, a vision of experience that emphasized the interconnection of perceiver and world could answer the original, basic questions of philosophy (questions such as Who are we? Where do we come from? Where are we going? etc.) without drawing false distinctions between inner and outer realms. This had been the strategy adopted by many of the ancient Greek philosophers, and Dewey followed their lead, especially in his later writings. For it was the logical outcome of a metaphysical position that, la Aristotle and many pre-Socratics, placed the concept of being in opposition to that of becoming, rather than nothingness. By the time Dewey began composing Experience and Nature, he had fully adopted this line of thought, as evidenced by his second chapter, Existence as Precarious and Stable. On such an account experience becomes a singular, holistic affair precisely because the interaction of live creature and environing conditions is involved in the very process of living. 34 However, according to Dewey, questions arose in the course of hundreds of years of philosophic inquiry because experience can always be turned inward on itself, it can be analyzed. [T]he act of observation may be inquired into and form a 33 EN, LW 1:11 [emphasis added] 34 AE, LW 10:42 [emphasis added] 20

PAGE 25

subject of study and become thereby a refined object of study. 35 As he charged, the result of such introspection, most often identified with Modern philosophy, is the tendency to draw distinctions, to separate experience into primary and secondary components, into the experienced and the experiencing. He rejected this tendency. As he wrote in 1917, it is just the inherited view of experience common to the empirical school and its opponents [i.e. the rationalist school] which keeps alive many discussions even of matters that are on their face quite remote from it, while it is also this view which is most untenable in the light of existing science and social practice. 36 Therefore he argued, contra British empiricism, that primary experience alone (i.e. the stream of sensory perceptions) is, by itself, ipso facto insufficient for analysis because of the very capacity for reflection that human beings possess, and, contra rationalism, that the notion of innate ideas is merely the result of a bias toward treating objects selected because of their value in some special context as the real. 37 As he saw it, For reflection the eventual is always better or worse than the given. But since it would also be better if the eventual good were now given, the philosopher, belonging by status to a leisure class relieved from the urgent necessity of dealing with conditions, converts the eventual into some kind of Being, something which is, even if does not exist Reflection determining preference for an eventual good has dialectically wrought a miracle of transubstantiation 38 The traditional subject-matter of philosophy, then, has either been experience (as a result of philosophical reflection) or attempts to solve the subsequent splintering of experience at the hands of reflection. More importantly, the problem philosophy 35 EN, LW 1:21 [Deweys emphasis] 36 MW 10:5 37 EN, LW 1:33 38 EN, LW 1:33 21

PAGE 26

must solve, if it ever hopes to recover its grip on the real world, is how to reunite the pieces of experience that have been torn asunder, viz. perception and reflection. Dewey tried to reunite these two by mapping out the natural, or generic, traits of experience, which, taken free of the restrictions imposed by other concepts, is full of inference. There is, apparently, no conscious experience without inference; reflection is native and constant. 39 He hoped that these traits would show perception and reflection to be inseparable. For him, the immense diversity of human affairs, interests, concerns, values which compartmentalists pigeonhole under religion aesthetics politics economics etc., etc. all share the same character of a integrated, transactional relationship between human beings and their surroundings. And, it was this general character that Dewey wanted to capture with his use of the term experience. To compose a complete list of the generic traits of experience that Dewey proposed would prove difficult. While perhaps the most extensive treatment of these traits can be found in Experience and Nature, Dewey never offered an exhaustive account. He would often seemingly create new ones, ad hoc, in order to make a point in some other line of argumentation. But, this may be explained when considered in light of the goal Dewey had in mind when introducing these traits, viz. to demonstrate how experience could be seen as inherently tied to culture. This point is of vital importance for his overall project, though one which has remained unclear in secondary literature. On one hand, Deweys seemingly egalitarian acceptance of cultures, even those wildly different from one another, might appear too culturally 39 MW 10:6 22

PAGE 27

relativistic to potential critics. In this regard, his vague presentation of the traits of experience could be cited as evidence. On the other hand, to attempt a comprehensive list of such traits would undermine the naturalistic conception of experience that Dewey hoped to put on the gold standard. After all, if experience is a natural affair, then it must adapt to changes in the environment, which would amount to most of its generic traits being wholly contingent. When understood naturalistically, i.e. as an organisms method of negotiating its way through an environment, the once limited concept of experience could be tied together with the broader concept of culture. With this in mind, I will briefly list only those traits that Dewey emphasized most and were most central to his notion of experience, rather than attempt to enumerate each of the generic traits that he identified in experience. Perhaps the two most important traits of experience for Dewey would be change and continuity. He characterized the first as being eventful, precarious, and hazardous. I have chosen change as a catchall for these descriptions. This could best be summed up by the doctrine of universal flux attributed to the pre-Socratic philosopher Heraclitus. However, it is important to note that the mantra One cannot step into the same river twice, so often associated with this doctrine, only partially represents the Heraclitean view. This version of the statement lends itself to the interpretation that all things are changing at all times and that even those things which appear stable are merely in a slower process of flux, one that escapes observation. But, on such an interpretation, since a river is constantly changing, one could not even step into the same river once. As recent scholarship has suggested, what Heraclitus may have meant when he wrote, On those stepping into rivers 23

PAGE 28

staying the same other and other waters flow, (Diels-Kranz B22) was that although different waters flow through a river, the river itself stays the same. And, more importantly, it is only by virtue of the flow that there is even a river at all instead of a pond or lake. 40 There is a governing form, in this case that of a river, that bounds the moments of change and connects them. When understood this way, the doctrine of universal flux jibes well with Deweys notion of change within experience. It is by virtue of the hazards and uncertainties that color experience, that the live creature has any experience at all. As Dewey put it, The doctrine of [Heraclitus], while it held that all things flow like a river and that change is so continuous that a man cannot step into the same river even once (since it changes as he steps), nevertheless also held that there is a fixed order which controls the ebb and flow of the universal tide. 41 This fixed order is what led Dewey to posit continuity as a generic trait of experience. On such a view, experience is not at all atomistic, but rather is pregnant with connections, i.e. experience continuously flows from one part to the next it is not simply a succession of events. This continuity, or stability, is of vital importance to experience, without it the moments of change would spill over into chaos. As Dewey wrote in Art as Experience, To overpass the limits that are set is destruction and death In a world of mere flux, change would not be cumulative; it would not move toward a close. Stability and rest would have no being. 42 But, this order is not fixed in the sense of being static; it is dynamic and rhythmic, fixed in 40 cf. Wheelwright, Philip Ellis. Heraclitus. New York: Oxford University Press, 1968. pgs. 29-36. and "Heraclitus," by Daniel W. Graham, Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, www.iep.utm.edu/ February 4 th 2005. 41 LW 14:101 42 AE, LW 10:22 24

PAGE 29

the sense of being directed and connective. Again, Dewey wrote, All interactions that effect stability and order in the whirling flux of change are rhythms. There is ebb and flow, systole and diastole: ordered change. The latter moves within bounds. 43 Elsewhere, Dewey likened the notion of continuity to a variable that remains constant in a mathematical equation, and as it is in math, he claimed, so it is in nature and life. 44 However, it is important to note that the movement toward a close to which Dewey alluded does not signify a move toward some ultimate end. Rather, for Dewey, it is a move toward an intermediate end-in-view which is itself, along with the means to attain it, still a part of experience. In this way, according to Dewey, experience is also historical, i.e. it has narrative characteristics which seem to raise particular events above the otherwise continuous flow of moments. An averted catastrophe, a meal enjoyed in Paris, a storm passed through on an oversea voyage, all exemplify the type of event which Dewey called, an experience. Such an event is historical insofar as, the points of its incidence shift in successive observations of it It carries on and is, therefore, instrumental as well as final. 45 Each of these experiences has a unique quality that defies communication, some attribute that is wholly immediate and therefore not an object of knowledge. Compare this with the postulate of immediate empiricism that things are what they are experienced as and it becomes clear that these qualities are not subjective, they belong, as Dewey 43 AE, LW 10:22 44 EN, LW 1:64 45 AE, LW 10:144 25

PAGE 30

asserted, both to the thing experienced and the one experiencing them. Dewey claimed that, In such experiences, every successive part flows freely, without seam and without unfilled blanks, into what ensues. At the same time there is no sacrifice of the self-identity of the parts. A river, as distinct from a pond, flows. But its flow gives a definiteness and interest to its successive portions greater than exist in the homogenous portions of a pond. In an experience, flow is from something to something. 46 Accordingly, experience consists, writ-large, of innumerably intertwined beginnings and endings in which these types of affairs may arise. Selective interest allows us to pick out which moments we will bundle up together out of the continuous flow to call an experience. When this happens, meaning is imparted to the event and it becomes communicative insofar as it directs us back to something beyond itself, namely the background of surrounding moments. Thus, another generic trait of experience is communication, or expression. The immediacy of the event is unified and heightened by the stable order of expression. Dewey tells us this is life in its most robust form. Experience in the degree in which it is experience is heightened vitality. Instead of signifying being shut up within one's own private feelings and sensations, it signifies active and alert commerce with the world; at its height it signifies complete interpenetration of self and the world of objects and events. Instead of signifying surrender to caprice and disorder, it affords our sole demonstration of a stability that is not stagnation but is rhythmic and developing. 47 Dewey refers to these heightened moments as consummatory experiences. But, the ambiguous verb to consummate and its noun derivative consummation can be 46 AE, LW 10:43 47 AE, LW 10:25 26

PAGE 31

misleading. On one hand, these can mean closure in the sense of completion or culmination as in the consummation of marriage. On the other hand, the verb can become an adjective that refers to something that is complete in the sense of needing no qualification, as in (pejoratively) the consummate fool, and it is this latter meaning, i.e. without qualification, that Dewey wished to evoke. A consummatory experience, on his view, is a grouping of moments that stand out from the rest of experience, like a great meal, a terrible storm, or a beautiful sculpture. Dewey called such a grouping an experience because it needs no further qualification. It stands alone as a representative of the rest of the moments surrounding it. These consummatory experiences serve as exemplars that structure our experience into manageable components, and since reflecting upon every moment in experience would prove impossible, we could not reflect upon anything at all without this ordered structure. That is not to say, however, that once an experience reaches consummation, that it has come to an end, but rather, as Dewey claimed, The time of consummation is also one of beginning anew. 48 Consummatory experiences, then, are pauses, not breaks, in the continuity of experience. This is how a rhythmic order is established. In rhythmic ordering, every close and pause, like the rest in music, connects as well as delimits and individualizes. A pause in music is not a blank, but is a rhythmic silence that punctuates what is done while at the same time it conveys an impulsion forward, instead of arresting at the point which it defines. 49 48 AE, LW 10:23 49 AE, LW 10:177 27

PAGE 32

But, this rhythmic order is not merely established temporally, The proportionate interception of changes establishes an order that is spatially patterned, as well. 50 If musical rhythm is the temporal analog to consummatory experience, then the spatial analog might be the rhythm of ocean waves. Each trough delimits each wave crest, but to say that waves are separated by troughs would belie fluid dynamics. On the micro level, water molecules are all connected in a processional, circular movement, on the macro level, troughs flow into waves and call attention to them, giving significance to each. If we understand this connection and are able to internalize it, we will operate with our surroundings more harmoniously. As Dewey put it, Contrast of lack and fullness, of struggle and achievement, of adjustment after consummated irregularity, form the drama in which action, feeling, and meaning are one Inner harmony is made only when, by some means, terms are made with the environment. 51 Because these consummatory experiences are dynamic, i.e. they move through experience with us, they can always be re-evaluated. The consummatory phase, therefore, is an ongoing process, it has duration and recurrence, and it can rise and subside in relation to the flow of experience. This feature of experience, that it can be consummatory, illustrates the formation of context. As Dewey wrote in Context and Thought, an essay that sits in his career roughly halfway between Experience and Nature and Art as Experience, Context includes at least those matters which for brevity I shall call background and selective interest Background is both temporal 50 AE, LW 10:22 51 AE, LW 10:22-3 28

PAGE 33

and spatial. 52 In what follows I will explicate how consummatory experience leads to the formation of context and what Dewey meant by calling context a background. Experience and Context What is of the greatest importance for Deweys account of experience is the context within which the experience takes place. But, what exactly is context? In Deweys philosophy it is, the whole environment of which philosophy must take account in all its enterprises. A background is implicit in some form and to some degree in all thinking, although as background it does not come into explicit purview; that is, it does not form a portion of the subject matter which is consciously attended to, thought of, examined, inspected, turned over. 53 But, merely calling it a background, offers little in the way of clarification. Dewey identified three manifestations of the background he referred to as context, each corresponding to a particular type of interaction within experience. The first manifestation of context, according to Deweys account, arises from the physical interaction of creatures with environments. The context of this interaction is the organism itself. As Dewey argued, the context of any experience is both organic, i.e. it is of and related to an experiencing organism, or live creature, as well as holistic, i.e. its organic aspects should not be separated from non-organic ones. He wrote, The organism, self, ego, subject, give it whatever name you choose, is implicated in all thinking as in all eating, business, or play. Since 52 LW 6:11 [emphasis added] 53 LW 6:11 29

PAGE 34

it cannot in its entirety be made an explicit object of reflection and yet since it affects all matters thought of, it is legitimately called a phase of context. 54 But, as we have seen, Dewey rejected the distinction between subject and object, and his use of terms commonly associated with subjectivity should therefore not be construed as a moment of hedging. He used these terms in this passage in order to distinguish between subjectivity understood as a kind of view from nowhere and subjectivity as a determining attitude or interest. Of the former he claimed, A standpoint which is nowhere in particular and from which things are not seen at a special angle is an absurdity, and of the latter, Interest, as the subjective, is after all equivalent to individuality or uniqueness. 55 The difference, according to Dewey, arises out of a special characteristic of subjectivity, viz. that although it is involved in all thinking it can never itself fully be made into an object of thought. 56 Subjectivity in this second sense, i.e. as selective interest, then, is a phase of context. Again, Dewey warns against letting selective interest run amok in philosophical thought, Thinking is always thinking, but philosophic thinking is, upon the whole, at the extreme end of the scale of distance from the active urgency of concrete situations. It is because of this fact that neglect of context is the besetting fallacy of philosophical thought. 57 But, as we saw above, selective interest is necessary in order to form a consummatory experience. So if we want to avoid letting selective interest run amok, it would seem, then, that selective interest is only desirable up to a limit. Dewey argued that selecting out of specific contexts, such as selecting a particularly good 54 LW 6:14 55 LW 6:14-5 56 Dewey followed Peirce in this regard. See for example Peirces Some Consequences of Four Incapacities. The Journal of Speculative Philosophy, vol. 2 1868, pgs. 140-157. 57 LW 6:17 30

PAGE 35

meal out of the context of a Parisian vacation, only becomes a problem when it is converted into abstraction from all context whatsoever. 58 This raises an issue of inclusion. Dewey implies that it is possible to select out of a particular context and yet still have that which has been selected be included within some still wider context. As we have seen, when the appropriate amount of selective interest is applied to the continuous flow of experiential moments an experience is formed. The ensuing background of that consummatory experience represents the second manifestation of context, viz. the background of consummatory experiences as such which arises out of the psychophysical interaction of experience that is known as reflection. If selective interest leads both to the formulation of consummatory experience and to context, then it would seem that experience is, in the very least, intimately related to context. But, Dewey claimed that in the most general terms, they are not merely related but are actually identical. As he put it, If the finally significant business of philosophy is the disclosure of the context of beliefs, then we cannot escape the conclusion that experience is the name for the last inclusive context. 59 In this broad sense, experience and context are synonymous. However, since Dewey saw experience as a matter of interaction between organisms and environments, perhaps a better word for context in this regard would be culture. And, if we understand culture as any particular groups body of knowledge and values, each of which involves belief, then the business of philosophy would be the disclosure of 58 LW 6:16 59 LW 6:20 31

PAGE 36

culture. Understood in this way, experience bestows meaning on an environment, meaning that can be transmitted to later generations. Once experience in general has gained these communicative, contextual qualities it can open up the possibility for new, less inclusive, contexts. As a result of this communicative interaction within experience, culture would represent the third and most inclusive manifestation of context. As Dewey wrote in an unfinished revision to the first chapter of Experience and Nature, The name "culture" in its anthropologicalsense designates the vast range of things experienced in an indefinite variety of ways. It possesses as a name just that body of substantial references which "experience" as a name has lost. 60 And, elsewhere he wrote, Were I to write (or rewrite) Experience and Nature today I would entitle the book Culture and Naturebecause of my growing realization that the historical obstacles which prevented understanding of my use of experience are, for all practical purposes, insurmountable. culture designatesthat immense diversity of human affairs. 61 Thus, for Dewey, such a view can be summed up in the single word contextualism. By making human affairs the primary focus of his empirical method, Dewey alleviated the need for explaining reality in its absolute form. Accordingly, subsequent transformations within philosophic inquiry can be viewed within the context of whatever problems are most pressing. This led Dewey to formulate a detailed account of inquiry, and it is that concept to which I will now turn. 60 LW 1:363 61 LW 1:361 32

PAGE 37

CHAPTER TWO INQUIRY: THE ENRICHMENT OF CONTEXT The search for the pattern of inquiry is, accordingly, not one instituted in the dark. It is checked and controlled by knowledge of the kinds of inquiry that have and have not worked; methods whichcan be so compared as to yield reasoned or rational conclusions. [LTI, LW 12:108] The Search for a Pattern In the preceding chapter, the first measure of Deweys naturalism that psychological states can be reduced to the interactions of organisms and environments within life-experience was shown to be the genesis of what he called context. Furthermore, it was argued that context, in this naturalistic sense, is synonymous with a broad conception of culture. However, prima facie, this point is still lacking in several facets. First, it fails to explain, given that human beings are so nearly identical in biological terms, why there are a multitude of cultures throughout the world, often co-existing in the same environment. Second, if experience and culture are indeed interchangeable, then it remains to be seen how experience could be characterized in terms of environment manipulation/accommodation something implicit in the notion of culture. Third, this account renders context a vague and amorphous concept, one hardly instructive enough to be called culture in anything but the broadest sense. However, according to Dewey, accounting for how an organism probes into a particular problem, viz. a pattern of inquiry, could assuage all of these concerns. Since solving problems, on his view, is itself a part of experience albeit a specialized part he first thought to explicate his theory of 33

PAGE 38

inquiry by presenting how it showed up within the various functional conditions, or modes, of experience. These modes are, according to Dewey, natural conditions that determine how organisms deal with the instability and precariousness of experience. In his earliest text concerning inquiry, Studies in Logical Theory (1903), Dewey set out on this project. There, he raised important questions about the relations between dominantly aesthetic, moral and affectional modes and subject-matters of experience and the cognitional mode and its specific subject-matter. 62 That volume marked the beginning of what Joseph Ratner, in 1939, referred to as Deweys recasting philosophy as a general logic of experience. 63 Although, in that volume, Dewey made mention of a number of modes, he never offered a comprehensive list. Just as was argued in the previous chapter in reference to the generic traits of experience, this lack should not lead us to call Deweys account patchwork; rather, it should be seen as an initial exploration into a new type of logic, the broad strokes of which needed to be worked out prior to the details. In fact, the majority of Deweys works between the 1903 Studies volume and his Logic: The Theory of Inquiry (1938) could each be seen as working out the details of one of the activities (ethics, art, religion, science, and politics) that arise out of the diverse modes of experience (the moral, aesthetic, religious, cognitive, and practical) all of 62 Anton, John. American Naturalism and Greek Philosophy. Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books, 2004. pg. 138 63 Cf. Ratner, Joseph. Deweys Conception of Philosophy. In The Philosophy of John Dewey: The Library of Living Philosophers, vol. 1. ed. By Paul Schilpp and Lewis Hahn. Lasalle, IL: Open Court, (3 rd edition) 1989. pg. 71 34

PAGE 39

which, taken together, comprise Deweys general logic of experience. When we take Deweys works severally, as Ratner put it, they very naturally group themselves into special (or specific) logics of the typical (or distinctive) modes of experience. Thus to mention only some of his representative works: Human Nature and Conduct is the special logic of the socio-ethical mode of experience; Art as Experience is the special logic of the esthetic mode; A Common Faith of the religious; The Quest for Certainty and Logic: The Theory of Inquiry comprise the special logic of the scientific mode of experience; The Public and Its Problems, Individualism Old and New, Liberalism and Social Action comprise the socio-practical or utilitarian; And finally Experience and Nature. [Therein] All modes of experience are naturally interconnected, being socio-cultural differentiations of common experience. 64 The insight of this passage deserves to be quoted at length. However, the last remark of the passage that the diverse modes of experience are naturally interconnected is perhaps the most informative. As Ratner explained, the modes of experience are, for Dewey, differentiations of a cultural kind, each of which imparts a specialized form of cultural intelligence interwoven into the fabric of common experience. Although Ratners account neatly ties together all of Deweys works between 1903 and 1938, we are left wondering many things about the modes of experience. For instance, if we take seriously the notion that experience flows as a unified whole, then are the modes merely tributaries of this flow, and if so then how do they arise? Moreover, are the various modes on par with one another, or does any one in particular subsume the others? It seems that Dewey may have struggled with these questions as well. In 1934, Dewey published two major works, Art as Experience and A Common Faith, each devoted to a particular mode (the aesthetic and religious 64 Ibid. [sic.] 35

PAGE 40

respectively) of experience. But, when read in tandem, these volumes could be viewed as slightly contradictory, i.e. each seems to laud its particular topic as the highest mode of experience. That is to say, one feasible conclusion that could be drawn from Art as Experience is that all experience is aesthetic. Likewise, it could be argued that one of the underlying themes in A Common Faith is that all experience is religious. However, these interpretations fail to account for the distinction Dewey made between general experience and an experience, i.e. those that are consummatory. A consummatory experience, as Dewey argued, serves as a representation of the surrounding moments of experience at large. A particular consummation may be valuable in relation to any one of the modes, it may be valuable within several, or it may change in time. For example, we may find a particular work of art important for aesthetic and religious reasons in our first encounter with it, and then only in some later encounter find some ethical or political value in it. With such a distinction between experience in general and an experience in mind, however, it becomes clear that each work is aimed at laying out the various features of the latter. Interestingly, however, it was only four years after the release of those two volumes that Dewey completed Logic: The Theory of Inquiry. That volume contained a marked difference in its treatment of the modes of experience. On one hand, Dewey clearly had moved beyond discussing the modes of experience in detail, and, on the other, wherever he did allude to them, they were treated as a mere outcome of either common sense or scientific inquiry. The arguments put forward in Logic were, as he put it, 36

PAGE 41

intended to indicate that the different objectives of common sense and of scientific inquiry demand different subject-matters and that this difference in subject matters is not incompatible with the existence of a common pattern in both types. 65 Thus, it would seem that by 1938 Dewey had abandoned the project of outlining the modes of experience, which had been initiated by Studies in Logical Theory. In response to Ratner, Dewey commented that, Dr. Ratner has put his finger upon the main shift in my writings. 66 Later in his response, Dewey responded to Ratner by highlighting the vital role that solving problems played for the development of his later work. I should, from the start, have systematically distinguished between knowledge as the outcome of special inquiries (undertaken because of the presence of problems) and intelligence as the product and expression of cumulative funding of the meanings reached in these cases. 67 Two points of clarification are called for here. The first is that there is a salient difference between knowledge and intelligence as outcome and habit of the cognitive mode of experience, and those that are the byproducts of non-cognitive modes. When taken as a product of these latter, non-cognitive modes, knowledge is strictly passive and intelligence manifests itself as a supplicatory method for dealing with problems, viz. tradition and all of the myths, rites, and superstitions that constitute it. On the other hand, when knowledge is the result of the cognitive (or scientific) mode, it is active, and intelligence manifests itself in the form of science and technology. This seems to answer the question of how different cultures can 65 LTI, LW 12:119 66 Dewey, John. Experience, Knowledge and Value. In The Philosophy of John Dewey: The Library of Living Philosophers, vol. 1. ed. By Paul Schilpp and Lewis Hahn. Lasalle, IL: Open Court, (3 rd edition) 1989. pg. 520 [LW 14:6] 67 Ibid. pg. 521 37

PAGE 42

respond to the same environment. Simply put, there are innumerable ways of coping with precariousness, but only one means for transforming it. The second point of clarification to be noted is that inquiry, understood in its broadest sense as the quality that all of the modes of experience share, only provides us with the type of intelligence that allow for the accommodation or avoidance of adversity. Although Dewey believed that everyday inquiry is continuous with the more specialized, cognitive type of inquiry, he argued that only the features displayed in scientific intelligence can give expertness of dealing with materials and tools, and promote the development of the experimental habit of mind. 68 In other words, only a cognitive mode of experience patterned after science can equip us with a means of transforming the environment and resolving its perils. This is the second measure of Deweys mature naturalism, and it serves as an answer to the concern that experience has no inherent feature of responding to environment. Deweys account of this pattern, like that of his conception of experience, developed gradually over the course of his career. Throughout his work after 1903, Dewey referred to it by several names, e.g. the empirical method, the new logic, experimentalism, and the pragmatic method. However, toward the end of his career, he returned to the generic term inquiry to encapsulate all of these. By 1938, Dewey admitted in the preface of Logic that this account does not have and could not have the finish and completeness that are theoretically possible. 69 But, he was convinced that it was so thoroughly sound that anyone who entertained it would, develop a theory of logic 68 RP, MW 12:86 69 LTI, LW 12:5 [emphasis added] 38

PAGE 43

that is in thorough accord with all the best authenticated methods of attaining knowledge. 70 Unfortunately, his account of the modes of experience has, by and large, remained on the fringes of Deweyan scholarship. But, if we put stock in Ratners account, as Dewey himself seemed to, then we may view Deweys Logic volume as the culmination of a theme that ran throughout the last half of Deweys career, i.e. that inquiry leads to a judgment of what to do, or what is to be done: a judgment respecting the future termination of an incomplete and in so far indeterminate situation. 71 The Indeterminate Situation as Impoverished Context According to Dewey, everyday life is an activity that requires great skill, We talk and read aloud, we get off and on street cars, we dress and undress, and do a thousand useful acts without thinking of them. 72 As we saw in the previous chapter, it was in Experience and Nature that Dewey first detailed the precarious features of experience within a dynamic environment. As he put it, Man finds himself living in an aleatory world; his existence involves, to put it baldly, a gamble. The world is a scene of risk; it is uncertain, unstable, uncannily unstable. Its dangers are irregular, inconstant, not to be counted upon as to their times and seasons. 73 By the time he penned Art as Experience, nine years and four major works later, Dewey was willing to put it in more urgent language. At every moment, the living creature is exposed to dangers from its surroundings, and at every moment it must 70 Ibid. 71 MW 8:30 [emphasis added] 72 HNC, MW 14:124 73 EN, LW 1:43 39

PAGE 44

draw upon something in its surroundings to satisfy its needs. 74 Perhaps it was this urgency that led him to move away from working out the various sub-logics of the modes of experience and turn to inquiry in general. Only four years later, Dewey presented his Logic: The Theory of Inquiry in which he offered a concrete definition of the process of stabilizing the aleatory world. As he defined it, Inquiry is the controlled or directed transformation of an indeterminate situation into one that is so determinate in its constituent distinctions and relations as to convert the elements of the original situation into a unified whole. 75 In order to understand this definition, however, we must first determine just what Dewey meant by the term indeterminate situation, which he referred to as the antecedent condition of inquiry. Perhaps a good illustration of the indeterminate situation could be found in the activity of using a computer. As we type on the keyboard and click the mouse, opening and closing programs, doing what is now known as multi-tasking, we give little or no consideration to the physical interaction with the machine itself, only to that which appears on the screen. However, when something goes wrong, e.g. the screen freezes or an error message appears, we become acutely aware of those activities that were, just moments before, hidden in the background of experience. We are suddenly faced with a situation that irritates us (not just in the sense that we are left cursing the name of Bill Gates, but also in that the activity of life has suddenly ground to a halt) and we must employ a measure of thoughtfulness to 74 AE, LW 10:19 75 LTI, LW 12:108 [emphasis added] 40

PAGE 45

escape. 76 This example highlights the contextual features of the indeterminate situation, which Dewey pointed out early on in his Logic, What is designated by the word "situation" is not a single object or event or set of objects and events. For we never experience nor form judgments about objects and events in isolation, but only in connection with a contextual wholean object or event is always a special part, phase, or aspect, of an environing experienced world a situation. 77 The situation, then, is a unity of meaningful commerce between an organism and its environment, a totality of significant relations that stays in the background of experience; it is, in a word, a context. The organism continues to be taken up with its surroundings until happenstance interrupts the flow of experience with uncertainty. The singular object stands out conspicuously because of its especially focal and crucial position at a given time in determination of some problem of use or enjoyment which the total complex environment presents. 78 In other words, immediate objects within this situation seem to object to any sort of physical manipulation, and the organism no longer finds itself comfortably situated within the environment. The problem, then, is that there is nothing within the context that can be applied to the situation in order to resolve indeterminacy; it lacks what could be called the contextual cues needed for further action. Simply put, the context lacks fullness, i.e. it is impoverished. Stating the matter in more personal terms, the organism is left flailing about, grasping at straws. As mentioned above, there may be many potential strategies for escaping the imposition of this impoverished context, 76 This example illustrates the striking similarities between Dewey and the early work of Martin Heidegger. (Cf. Heidegger, Martin. Being and Time. Translated by Joan Stambaugh. Albany, NY: SUNY Press. 1996. pgs. 72-76, wherein Heidegger discusses the breaking of a hammer.) 77 LTI, LW 12:72 [Deweys emphasis] 78 LTI, LW 12:108 41

PAGE 46

e.g. supplication, accommodation, or tradition such are the outcomes of the various non-cognitive modes however, each is tantamount to avoidance. But, where these fail, the organism could be forced to employ what Dewey called discourse through use of symbols in order to escape. 79 On his view, interruption opens up a space that is not only open to inquiry, but it is open in the sense that its constituents do not hang together. 80 This open space is the indeterminate situation. Dewey claimed that it was the open nature of an indeterminate situation that elicits inquiry to be questionable; or in terms of actuality instead of potentiality, to be uncertain, unsettled, disturbed. 81 It is important to note that, on Deweys account, it is the situation that exhibits these qualities. Indeterminacy is not simply a personal state of doubt, nor is it merely an affair of objects; rather, indeterminacy involves an interaction. For Nature is an environment only as it is involved in interaction with an organism, or self, or whatever name be used. 82 This is important because Dewey believed that when we move from indeterminate to determinate situations we are not merely adapting to meet the needs of the environment, nor are we adjusting the environment to meet our needs, but rather the result of inquiry is a transformation of both. The Pattern Of Inquiry According to Dewey, transformation of the indeterminate situation to determinate is active and operational wherever, 79 LTI, LW 12:109 Dewey added, In received logical terminology, propositions, or terms and the relations between them, are intrinsically involved. 80 Ibid. 81 Ibid. [Deweys emphasis] 82 LTI, LW 12:110 42

PAGE 47

Organic interaction becomes inquiry when existential consequences are anticipated; when environing conditions are examined with reference to their potentialities; and when responsive activities are selected and ordered with reference to actualization of some of the potentialities, rather than others, in a final existential situation. 83 Granted, that in responding to an indeterminate situation like our computer example above the desired outcome is an absence of irritation, however, the natural desire for a psychological state of comfort is only the mechanism that helps us stand up against indeterminacy. It is the employment of intelligence through inquiry that allows us to actually escape an indeterminate situation. Dewey first outlined the pattern of inquiry in his Democracy and Education (1916), where he identified five constitutive steps: (i) perplexity, confusion, doubt, due to the fact that one is implicated in an incomplete situation whose full character is not yet determined; (ii) a conjectural anticipation--a tentative interpretation of the given elements, attributing to them a tendency to effect certain consequences; (iii) a careful survey (examination, inspection, exploration, analysis) of all attainable consideration which will define and clarify the problem in hand; (iv) a consequent elaboration of the tentative hypothesis to make it more precise and more consistent, because squaring with a wider range of facts; (v) taking one stand upon the projected hypothesis as a plan of action which is applied to the existing state of affairs: doing something overtly to bring about the anticipated result, and thereby testing the hypothesis. 84 These could be summed up as doubt, interpretation, survey, elaboration and action. He believed these steps could occur in sequence or telescope together in 83 LTI, LW 12:111 84 DE, MW 9:157 [list format added] 43

PAGE 48

simultaneity, depending on the complexity of the situation. 85 But, no matter how they occurred temporally, all five steps were required for inquiry to take place. By 1938, however, Dewey had slightly revised these five steps. In his Logic volume, he outlined six steps, instead of the previous five each of which can still easily be fit into the revised list. 86 The first of these he identified as the indeterminate situation itself, which, of course, includes the perplexity and doubt that comprise (i) in the above list. However, it also conveys the interactional aspects of indeterminacy that those earlier, more subjective terms lacked. The second step in Deweys revised list was what he called the institution of a problem. Simply put, this refers to the clear statement of a problem and probably best corresponds to step (iii) in the above list. Dewey claimed, however, that it would have been proleptic to call the indeterminate situation a problematic one since it only becomes problematic in the very process of being subjected to inquiry. 87 Unfortunately in the academic world, as Dewey pointed out, too many [p]roblems that are self-set are mere excuses for seeming to do something intellectual. 88 Concerning this tendency, Dewey claimed, It is a familiar and significant saying that a problem well put is half-solved. 89 Dewey admitted, however, that clearly stating a problem would only get the inquirer so far, the determining of a genuine 85 cf. HWT, LW 6:238 86 cf. LTI, LW 12:109-120 87 LTI, LW 12:111 88 LTI, LW 12:112 89 Ibid. 44

PAGE 49

problem is a progressive inquirywhere much prior ingestion and digestion have occurred 90 This led him to the third step in his 1938 account, viz. the determination of a problem solution. In this vein, Dewey claimed that any situation that is altogether indeterminate would not lend itself to transformation. In order to get from indeterminacy to determinacy, then, requires the recognition of those factors in the situation or as Dewey put it, the facts of the case that are still determinate. This amounts to what could be called the formulation of a hypothesis, and includes both steps (ii) and (iv) from above. Explicating this step led Dewey to define ideas as anticipated consequences. Dewey simply called the fourth step in his revised account reasoning. His view of reasoning, however, was modeled after the Greek account of logos, insofar as it emphasized both rational and linguistic features. He argued that there was a double-aspect to experienced objects, since, on one hand, they are just what they are experienced as, and on the other, they indicate a relation to other objects in fulfilling some goal. 91 This latter is a process of operating with signs, i.e. it is inherently logical. As he put it, When communication occurs, all natural events are subject to reconsideration and revision; they are re-adapted to meet the requirements of conversation, whether it be public discourse or that preliminary discourse termed thinking. Events turn into objects, things with a meaning Events when once they are named lead an independent and double life. 92 90 Ibid. [Deweys emphasis] 91 cf. MW 6:458 92 EN, LW 1:132 45

PAGE 50

On his view, when a future possibility is seen as an anticipated consequence, the conclusion reached is not grounded, even if it happens to be correct. The check upon immediate acceptance is the examination of the meaning as a meaning. 93 In other words, the hypothesis that was formulated in the previous step of inquiry, Dewey argued, must be developed in relation to other conceptual structures. For him, even the dumb pang of an ache can achieve significance, i.e. meaning, when it becomes representational. This process of transforming events into signs is the consummation of experience par excellence, and illustrates one of the generic traits of experience, viz. the communicative. 94 When it occurs in the indeterminate situation, a prediction about the outcome of experimentation can be posited. And, as he put it, not following this step will be the end of inquiry insofar as the hypothesis is not developed in terms of the constellation of meanings to which it belongs, and such a failure can lead only to overt response. 95 This step best corresponds with the first part of (v) above, i.e. it consists in taking a stand on a projected hypothesis. Because he believed that events held a double life (the concrete one of existence and the abstract one of meaning), Dewey identified the fifth step in the pattern of inquiry as, the operational character of facts-meanings. Prima facie, it may appear strange to combine two seemingly disparate terms such as fact and meaning. However, Dewey believed that, within the process of inquiry, facts are 93 LTI, LW 12:115 94 This sentiment perhaps is a precursor to the shift toward language in 20 th century philosophy and is echoed in Wilfrid Sellars phrase, all awareness is a linguistic affair. Cf. Sellars, Wilfrid. Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science. (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press) vol. 1, 95 LTI, LW 12:116, This will become important in following chapter in regards to distinguishing between cognitive and non-cognitive habits. 46

PAGE 51

always operational in that they are selected with respect to a purpose or goal. Dewey had this to say about facts in their capacity as meanings, The operative force of facts is apparent when we consider that no fact in isolation has evidential potency. Facts are evidential and are tests of an idea in so far as they are capable of being organized with one another. The organization can be achieved only as they interact with one another. 96 On this view, facts are tied to meaning through the process of inquiry. As Dewey put it, Naming them operational is but a theoretical recognition of what is involved when inquiry satisfies the conditions imposed by the necessity for experimentation. 97 What this amounts to can best be summed up by the second part of step (v) above, viz. doing something overtly to bring about the anticipated result, and thereby testing the hypothesis. Dewey asserted that when inquiry is successful, the indeterminate is returned to determinate, but, if it is unsuccessful, then we must return to the third step, reinterpret the situation with this new information, and formulate a new hypothesis. The Determinate Situation as Enriched Context The sixth and final step in Deweys revised list is what he termed common sense and scientific inquiry. This step occurs only when inquiry successfully satisfies the problem at hand. In reference to this step, Dewey again distinguished between (common-sense) inquiry that is done within the non-cognitive modes of experience and the (scientific) inquiry that is done within the cognitive mode. Of the former, he wrote, 96 LTI, LW 12:117 [Deweys emphasis] 97 Ibid. 47

PAGE 52

They form a system but the system is practical rather than intellectual. It is constituted by the traditions, occupations, techniques, interests, and established institutions of the group. The meanings that compose it are carried in the common everyday language of communication between members of the group. The meanings involved in this common language system determine what individuals of the group may and may not do in relation to physical objects and in relations to one another. They regulate what can be used and enjoyed and how use and enjoyment shall occur. 98 So, the downside to common sense inquiry is that it yields a very narrow set of solutions, i.e. the traditions and techniques it produces will disclose only a limited number of possible solutions. Conversely, scientific inquiry, according to Dewey, frees meaning from the interests of a particular group and allows meaning to become more abstract where semantic coherence, as such, is the controlling consideration. 99 What issues forth is a pattern of reasoning that guides our inquiry vis--vis subsequent indeterminate situations. And, while this may also amount to a set of norms or imperatives, each is accepted or rejected only in terms of coherence with one another. This opens up the set of possible solutions to a problem. The difference between these types of norms and the traditional type could also be seen as one of form versus content. While common sense inquiry might provide content that is specific to the immediate needs of a particular group, it lacks a definite, repeatable structure. Scientific inquiry, on the other hand, provides a definite structure, or form, that can be used over and over in conjunction with new contents. What is true of both forms of inquiry, however, is that the last step in each amounts to the assimilation of a solution back into the original context. In the former 98 LTI, LW 12:118 99 LTI, LW 12:119 48

PAGE 53

type, i.e. common sense inquiry, the assimilation is in reference to specific, immediate, environing conditions. It is a temporary solution; it is, in a very real sense, a quick fix to the problem at hand. In scientific inquiry, however, assimilation occurs on a more general, abstract scale. The solutions garnered from it may be applicable across an array of indeterminate situations. But, just as the traditions and customs that are the product of common sense inquiry can limit the set of possible solutions, so too can the norms of scientific inquiry whenever they are viewed as foundations. Dewey warned against viewing these abstractions as static, eternal and immovable entities. As he put it, Every such interaction [i.e. inquiry] is a temporal process, not a momentary cross-sectional occurrence. 100 Whereas common sense inquiry is a process of accommodation by the organism to meet the demands of the environing conditions, cognitive inquiry is a process of adjustment in the situation, in terms of both the environment and the organism. 101 The result of which is an increase in complexity for both. Dewey described it as, The temporal quality of inquiry means, then, something quite other than that the process of inquiry takes time. It means that the objective subject-matter of inquiry undergoes temporal modification. 102 Twenty-two years earlier, in Democracy and Education, Dewey had referred to this temporal modification as plasticity, and described it therein as the capacity to retain and carry over from prior experience factors which modify subsequent 100 LTI, LW 12:110 101 cf. CF, LW 9:12 102 LTI, LW 12:122 [emphasis added] 49

PAGE 54

activities. 103 In his later work, Dewey would refer to this as the capacity for habit-formation. As he put it in Experience and Nature, We find also in all these higher organisms that what is done is conditioned by consequences of prior activities; we find the fact of learning or habit-formation. In consequence, an organism acts with reference to a time-spread, a serial order of events, as a unit, just as it does in reference to a unified spatial variety. Thus an environment both extensive and enduring is immediately implicated in present behavior. Operatively speaking, the remote and the past are "in" behavior making it what it is. 104 Thus, any transformation of the indeterminate into the determinate is a process of once again returning to a unified whole, except that, qua the outcome of cognitive inquiry, the determinate situation is a context that has been enriched, i.e. it has gained structure, through the development of a new habit. In the next chapter, this aspect of Deweys thought, i.e. the formation of habits, will be considered in detail. 103 DE, MW 9:47 104 EN, LW 1:213 50

PAGE 55

CHAPTER THREE GROWTH: THE OUTCOME OF CONTEXT AND THE PRAGMATIC METHOD We do not form habits, ordinarily, because we repeat, but we repeat because we have formed habits. A habit formed simply by repetition is very likely to be the undesirable sort of habit that which is likely to be our master instead of being our servant. [LW 17:299-300] The Importance of Habit With the theoretical groundwork of Deweys contextualism in place, we may now turn our attention toward the discussion initiated in the preface of this analysis, viz. how his notion of context relates to the pragmatic method. Dewey often treated the reconstruction of habit as synonymous with pragmatic method. In order to understand why Dewey held habits in such high regard, it will be helpful to trace some of the more important influences on his unique stance. Reconstructing habit for Dewey, however, involves the distinction, which was touched upon in the previous chapter, between habits as the product of cognitive inquiry (i.e. inquiry that is done within the cognitive mode of experience) and those that are the outcome of the other, non-cognitive inquiries (i.e. inquiries made from within the moral, practical, religious, or aesthetic modes of experience.) Establishing such a distinction will inevitably lead to Deweys concept of growth, which he considered to be dependent upon habit reconstruction. Arguably, the idea of growth (as the outcome of cognitive habit reconstruction) is both the single most important and most misunderstood strand running throughout Deweys philosophical, psychological and 51

PAGE 56

pedagogical interests, the one that ties these interests together in terms of context. Unfortunately, many Dewey scholars choose to cast aside his work on growth, and focus instead on the less amorphous concepts of experience and inquiry. 105 The final aim of this exegesis, therefore, will be to clarify how growth is the outcome of Deweys context. Just as Deweys views of experience and inquiry developed slowly over the course of several decades of writing, so too did his notion of habit. Throughout his career, the three concepts evolved symbiotically alongside one another. His first philosophical treatment of habit appeared in the years just following James release of The Principles of Psychology (1890), which made use of the term to undergird a type of psychological functionalism, and which Dewey admired for its rejection of many psychological dualisms. Simply put, functionalism is the theory that mental processes can be understood only in terms of usefulness. During the nine years after James Principles and leading up to his own Psychology and Social Practice (1899), Dewey wrote about habits in a resolutely behaviorist tone. Viewing habits through such a lens led him to question traditional notions of self, freedom, and necessity via James functionalist principles. His 1893 essay, The Superstition of Necessity, is an excellent indicator of this. There he identified the fallacy of the necessitarian as conflating what is determinate, in the sense of fully defined, with the cosmological belief in causation frequently called determinism. In this manner, Dewey characterized necessity as a 105 Cf. Forget Emerson, Forget Growth, Embrace Anaximander: Pragmatism and the Tragic Sense By Raymond D. Boisvert. Proceedings of the 2002 Society for the Advancement of American Philosophy Conference. www.americanphilosophy.org/archives/2002_Conference/2002_papers/boisvert_saito.htm Mar. 6 th 2005. 52

PAGE 57

useful go-between term, i.e. one that was useful in explaining why two seemingly unrelated concepts were actually related, but When it has succeeded, its value is nil. 106 There, Dewey said of necessity, When we say something or other must be so and so, the must does not indicate anything in the nature of the fact itself, but a trait in our judgment of that fact; it indicates the degree with which we have succeeded in making a whole out of the various elements which have to be taken into account in forming the judgment. More specifically, it indicates a half-way stage. 107 On Deweys account, causal necessity is merely the connection we make between two seemingly unconnected ideas, it is a go-between, the mid-wife of judgment and is only useful insofar as it links up one part of a whole with another part, but once that link is made it is no longer helpful in our understanding of the whole. Like Hume before him, Dewey argued that necessity was the name for our habit of getting carried away by the constitution of a whole by its various parts and thus talking about the parts as causing the whole rather than merely making it up. 108 Dewey claimed that this conflating of whole-part relationships with causal links can be a hindrance to human inquiry because, objects as they are for us, as known, [must] change with the development of our judgments. 109 But, when necessity is taken to be an essential component of the universe then, as he put it, Once the Ptolemaic conception is well rooted, cycles and epicycles, almost without end, are superadded, rather than reconstruct the original object. 110 106 EW 4:20 107 EW 4:20 [Deweys emphasis] 108 This is the tendency that Dewey labeled the necessitarian fallacy. 109 EW 4:22 110 EW 4:24 53

PAGE 58

Deweys proposal was that we strip the notion of necessity of any ontological (real world) status that it might enjoy and instead view it as a useful tool in helping us reconstruct theories whenever new data arise. He believed that it is often easier for us to form a new theory than to continue to heap exceptions-to-the-rules upon old ones. 111 He believed that if we could adopt this principle of action, then perhaps we could avoid the stagnations in thought, i.e. stagnations of convention, that have caused some of the greatest suffering in history. And, it was from within this Humean line of reasoning that Dewey first considered the reconstruction of habit. In that initial treatment, found in The Psychology of Effort (1897), he referred to reconstruction as a process of adaptation to new conditions by bodily states of action. 112 This accentuates the connotations of habit as it is used in its verb form, meaning to dwell or to reside. And, Deweys interest in habit becomes even more apparent when one considers its etymological connection with terms related to the notion of environment (terms like habitat and inhabit) so prevalent in Deweys work. However, Deweys work in education in the latter half of the 1890s, particularly his involvement in the Laboratory School at the University of Chicago, led him to develop this position even further before the turn of the century. Observing the difference that education could make on habituated conduct, Dewey rejected the one-directional view of habit, i.e. one that posited habit as merely the outcome of conditioning stimuli, in favor of a more dynamic and socially integrated 111 Thomas Kuhns work in The Structure of Scientific Revolutions crystallized this sentiment in the concept of paradigm. 112 EW 5:162 54

PAGE 59

interpretation. This was the view he defended in Psychology and Social Practice (1899), The School and Society (1900), and The Child and the Curriculum (1902). In those essays, Dewey decried the prevalent psychological models for their failure to provide an intelligible account of child psychology. Those models, on his account, tried to explain the psychological disposition of children in reference to adult psychological standards. As he put it in Psychology and Social Practice, [The child] is engaged in forming habits rather than in definitely utilizing those already formed. Consequently he is absorbed in getting that all-around contact with persons and things, that range of acquaintance with the physical and ideal factors of life, which shall afford the background and material for the specialized aims and pursuits of later life. He is, or should be, busy in the formation of a flexible variety of habits whose sole immediate criterion is their relation to full growth. This suggests that, in a sense, habits can be seen as prior to stimuli, i.e. the child already possesses the capacity for habits before stimuli that bring that capacity into fruition ever appear. Habits, on this view, are pulled from the front by biological and social factors, rather than pushed from behind by factors that were traditionally explained in the language of physics or theology. In other words, Dewey believed that human beings were creatures of habit, but he saw habits as potentialities that were antecedent to experience rather than a byproducts of rote action. Habits, for Dewey, are pulled from the front insofar as they are only fixed by their fruitfulness in attaining future ends, much as genetic mutations in species are only fixed when they provide some marginal aid in adapting to environmental changes. This realization jibed well with Deweys already heavily Darwinian leanings and was reinforced by his rejection of the empiricists fallacy in his essay on the reflex arc 55

PAGE 60

concept. He concluded that determinism and psychological functionalism were incompatible insofar as the latter portrayed habits as a sort of feedback loop that undermined the traditional view of causality on which the former depended by showing that habits and environment shape one another. For Dewey, this point further undermined the notion of causality, and he quickly ruled determinism out of court. 113 As Dewey would later write in Experience and Nature, The reality is the growth-process itself; childhood and adulthood are phases of a continuity, in which just because it is a history, the later cannot exist until the earlier exists ("mechanistic materialism" in germ); and in which the later makes use of the registered and cumulative outcome of the earlier--or, more strictly, is its utilization ("spiritualistic teleology" in germ). The real existence is the history in its entirety, the history as just what it is. The operations of splitting it up into two parts and then having to unite them again by appeal to causative power are equally arbitrary and gratuitous. 114 Forming Habits Through Inquiry By the time he had released Democracy and Education in 1916, Dewey had fully adopted a biological/social stance on habit formation, i.e. one that emphasized the feedback loop aspect of habits. There, he referred to the capacity to form habits as the innate plasticity of human beings and laid the groundwork for the distinction between cognitive and non-cognitive habits that would be the touchstone of his idea of inquiry. As he explained therein, responding to a problematic situation like our 113 In The Metaphysical Club, Louis Menand speculated that the death of Deweys young son, Morris, was the main catalyst in his educational interests, since Dewey had written in some of his personal correspondence with family that he was becoming a student of his sons growth. In a similar fashion, one could hypothesize that Deweys rejection of determinism, which followed on the heels of Morris death in 1895, was another outcome of the loss. Of course, such a claim can only remain purely conjecture, as Dewey was not prone to writing about himself in an emotionally revealing manner. What is clear, however, is that for whatever reason, by 1900 Dewey had begun to view habits as a fundamental part of human character and thus he set out to examine them in detail. 114 EN, LW 1:210 56

PAGE 61

computer example from the preceding chapter is brought about by the natural desire to alleviate indeterminacy. In this regard, Dewey followed Peirce in the belief that uncertainty was an irritation that human beings were compelled to avoid. However, Dewey argued that the natural desire for a psychological state of comfort is merely a mechanism that helps us stand up against indeterminacy. In other words, instincts, on Deweys view, are not foundational; they are merely elements in habits. 115 What is needed in order to actually relieve the irritation, then, is a means of getting back in synchronicity with the environment. The natural way of dealing with objects that arise in the problematic situation is in terms of value, i.e. they either have positive or negative value in regard to escaping indeterminacy. For Dewey, value is a product of inquiry, yet it arises from an inquiry that is made from within a non-cognitive mode of experience. There is nothing no fact, object, or entity that has intrinsic value antecedent to whatever purpose the situation brings to the table. The philosopher, carpenter, artist, and environmentalist all view a particular tree in different ways, but it would be senseless to assert that any one of them sees the tree as it is in itself. The tree is valuable, of course, regardless of whichever view one takes, but its value is always dependent on a particular end. So, the environmentalist may value the tree because of its ability to slow erosion, the artist for its symmetry, the carpenter for the quality of the wood, and the philosopher because of the noise it might not make when it falls, but each values the tree for the function it fulfills in attaining some end. Dewey called this type of transaction with ones surroundings, valuation. Simply put, valuation involves the habit, or capacity, of ranking several 115 HNC, MW 14:61 57

PAGE 62

preferences in the order of which will be most beneficial in alleviating the irritation of indeterminacy. But, this habit is only a proto-process of means-ends manipulation, it lacks the more complex capacity of dealing with objects as abstract signs, and as such, Dewey saw it as affective rather than cognitive. 116 While the affective types of strategy toward indeterminacy may involve minimal cognitive capacity, since it gets worked out in terms of concrete conditions available for its realization, i.e. in terms of means, it still cannot provide knowledge, but only a type of repeatable norm, i.e. a value that can help avoid indeterminacy. 117 On Deweys view, only the employment of a habit that has been formed by inquiry from within the cognitive mode of experience the habit he called intelligence can allow for an actual transformation of an indeterminate situation. The habits of valuation alone do not offer the requisite tools for transformation. But, against the traditional view which treated intelligence as synonymous with the faculty of reason and, subsequently, as inherent within human beings (a priori is the technical term), Dewey claimed that intelligence is not prior to experience. He often referred to intelligence in terms of reasonableness rather than as an a priori faculty. This difference places emphasis on the activity of intelligence. On his account, an inquirer may do something reasonable, such as choosing to build a boat out of teakwood planks, or something unreasonable, such as crafting a similar vessel out of 116 There have been many thinkers who sought to cast aside the fact-value distinction. On such a view, there would be no clear delineation between subject and object or between "ought" and "is." Dewey was one such thinker. He argued that the relationship between facts and values resembles a spectrum more than it does one of polar opposites. There are many things on the fact side of that spectrum. But, even those things have some value imparted to them by the organism, through the process of valuation. Likewise, those things that sit pretty far on the value side, e.g. the morally or aesthetically praiseworthy, still have some fact of the matter about them. 117 HNC, MW 14:217 [emphasis added] 58

PAGE 63

matchsticks. In either case, value has guided action, but only when judged against a particular end (in this case boat-building) is the reasonableness of an action demonstrable. Knowledge, on the traditional view, is either something found in the world or in the mind. For Dewey, though, knowledge is the outcome of an inquiry wherein the habits of intelligence transform indeterminate situations into determinate ones. In other words, all knowledge even that which has been traditionally termed prepositional is essentially a skill, one acquired through developing appropriate habits. Perhaps Deweys most robust expression of habit can be found in his 1922 work, Human Nature and Conduct, a third of which was devoted to the topic. There, Dewey described habits in the same kind of interactional terms that he would continue to use in Experience and Nature, Art as Experience, and Logic: The Theory of Inquiry. To illustrate, he wrote habits are like [physiological] functions in many respects, and especially in requiring the cooperation of organism and environment habits are arts They are working adaptations of personal capacities with environing forces. 118 This echoes the view laid out in Democracy and Education that habits are social functions. Yet, in Human Nature, Dewey made strides to describe further the relation between the social function of habits and inquiry, which he accomplished by identifying it in terms of meaning rather than value. Talking about meaning allows for consequences of actions to be re-evaluated whenever necessary, whereas talking 118 HNC, MW 14:15-16 59

PAGE 64

about value implies reference to a realm of transcendent essences that Dewey wished to avoid. As he put it, [Children] owe to adults the opportunity to express their native activities in ways which have meaning. Even if by some miracle original activity could continue without assistance from the organized skill and art of adults, it would not amount to anything. It would be mere sound and fury. In short, the meaning of native activities is not native; it is acquired. It depends upon interaction with a mature social medium. 119 This shift in emphasis from value to meaning is important for two reasons. First, because Dewey believed it better conveyed the formation of habits in a non-instinctual light, one that could more readily account for the diversity of cultures found in various environments. According to him, Admission that the idea of, say, standing erect [an activity usually identified as completely instinctual] is dependent upon sensory materials is, therefore equivalent to recognition that it is dependent upon the habitual attitudes which govern concrete sensory materials. The medium of habit filters all the material that reaches our perception and thought. The filter is not, however, chemically pure. It is a reagent which adds new qualities and rearranges what is received. Our ideas truly depend upon experience, but so do our sensations. And the experience upon which they both depend is the operation of habits--originally of instincts. 120 He saw the view that instincts were separable and thus antecedent to habits as yet another instance of the empiricists fallacy. On his view, it would be erroneous to believe that instincts precede habits simply because such seems to be the case when an individual is considered in isolation from society. For, he believed that if an individual be isolated in this fashion, along with the fact of primacy of instinct we 119 HNC, MW 14:65 120 HNC, MW 14:26 60

PAGE 65

find also the fact of death. 121 Diversity, then, comes from the fact that native stock has been modified by interaction with different environments, both natural and social, not from a difference in native capacities or instincts. Cultural differences can arise within the same natural environment because habits can be formed from within any one of the modes of experience, as our tree example above illustrated. 122 But, as we have seen from Deweys view of experience, the difference among environments should be couched in temporal as well as spatial terms, since the environment in which the act takes place is never twice alike. 123 On Deweys account, the differences of objective result that stem from the differences in the surrounding environment (both living and non-living) are the only components of the meaning of the act. 124 As we saw in the previous chapter, Dewey claimed that the fourth step in cognitive inquiry involved the examination of meaning as meaning. 125 This presents the second benefit of shifting from value terms to meaning terms when talking about habit formation, i.e. the latter can better capture the fluidity of the interaction between organisms and environments insofar as meanings, like consummatory experiences, can always be re-evaluated as they move through experience with us. Realizing this, Dewey thought, could protect against the calcification of the means-end distinction. Thus, Dewey referred to all ends as ends-in-view, because, regardless of what mode of inquiry an organism employs, it can only respond to indeterminacy by surveying the possible outcomes that are in view 121 HNC, MW 14:68 122 HNC, MW 14:67 123 HNC, MW 14:105 124 HNC, MW 14:105 [Deweys emphasis] 125 LTI, LW 12:115 61

PAGE 66

of its particular set of habits. Thus, we see the major difference between habits as the outcome of cognitive inquiry and those of the non-cognitive variety. The habits which are employed in the former, which Dewey called intelligence, involve manipulation of abstract symbols, or meanings, whereas the latter involve the manipulation of values, which are always more proximate than meanings. In other words, cognitive habits form the principles of thought, on which logic and mathematics are based. Non-cognitive habits form the principles of normativity, on which aesthetics and ehtics are based. The former yield knowledge, the latter attitudes. Habit Reconstruction and Growth Although both types of inquiry can lead to the formation of habits, only the cognitive variety can lead to the type of re-evaluation of its habits that Dewey referred to as reconstruction. It achieves this through the versatility of meaning. As Dewey put it, The more numerous our habits the wider the field of possible observation and foretelling. The more flexible they are, the more refined is perception in its discrimination and the more delicate the presentation evoked by imagination. 126 Because cognitive inquiry employs habits that deal with meaning, this type of inquiry can lead to the changing of those habits whenever they produce a solution that does not cohere with other meanings. This is where experimentation, which Dewey believed was merely a description of the default setting in which all live creatures operated, comes into focus within his account. As he had explained over a 126 HNC, MW 14:123 62

PAGE 67

decade earlier, in his How We Think (1910), when any organism is presented with a series of events it will inevitably relate them to past experiences. Dewey claimed that the limitation of valuation within non-cognitive modes of experience is that it affords no way of discriminating between right and wrong conclusions. 127 Thus, by itself, it does not provide the habits of deciding between simple conclusions such as phlogiston or opiums dormative powers against more complex explanations such as combining oxygen with a combustible or a chemical reaction in the brain. Cognitive inquiry, on the other hand, has an apparatus for distinguishing between competing theses. This apparatus is the habit of abstraction, or meaning manipulation. As Dewey put it, Experiment is the chief resource in scientific reasoning because it facilitates the picking out of significant elements in a gross, vague whole. 128 He thought new interpretations arose through experimentation in response to particular problems. The difference, in the end, between cognitive inquiry and non-cognitive valuation boils down to the ability to create new habits via new interpretations of the meaning of action. Thus, habit reconstruction amounts to the ability to create new habits through interpretation. The creation of new habits is, in general terms, what Dewey referred to as growth. In his words, Habits take the form both of habituation, or a general and persistent balance of organic activities with the surroundings, and of active capacities to readjust activity to meet new conditions. The former furnishes the background of growth; the latter constitute growth. 129 127 HWT, MW 6:294 128 HWT, MW 6:298 129 DE, MW 9:57 63

PAGE 68

As stated above, this general notion of growth was featured prominently in most of Deweys writings, especially the moral and pedagogic ones. Perhaps a definition, in this general sense, could be found in Democracy and Education, where Dewey called growth the cumulative movement of action toward a later result. 130 This definition, however, is perhaps too vague. With it, Dewey did not mean to reinstate what he saw as a false idea of growth or development, that it is a movement toward a fixed goal. 131 And with this in mind, he claimed, Growth is [mistakenly] regarded as having an end, instead of being an end. 132 On his view, then, growth has no end beyond itself. 133 Throughout both Democracy and Education and Human Nature and Conduct, Dewey laid out many of the conditions of growth in hope of establishing a more detailed description. Two of these conditions have already been discussed in this analysis, viz. the need for others and plasticity. These are most visibly featured in Democracy and Education because of Deweys belief that both of these conditions are at their height in childhood and youth. 134 But, the primary condition of growth, for him, was immaturity, which he claimed includes the notions of capacity and potentiality. According to Dewey, immaturity, like capacity and like potentiality, is not properly understood as a negative term. Capacity may denote mere receptivity, like the capacity of a quart measure. We may mean by potentiality a merely dormant or quiescent state--a capacity to become something different under external influences. But we also mean by capacity an ability, a 130 DE, MW 9:46 131 DE, MW 9:55 132 Ibid. 133 DE, MW 9:57 134 DE, MW 9:57 64

PAGE 69

power; and by potentiality potency, force. Now when we say that immaturity means the possibility of growth, we are not referring to absence of powers which may exist at a later time; we express a force positively present--the ability to develop. 135 The upshot of this view is not only process that growth is a process of becoming, but that it is a process of becoming that ought not reach a point of terminus. Although growth is the transformation of the indeterminate to the determinate, this should not suggest once this transformation has taken place that growth has ended. And, this point is the reason Dewey warned against interpreting consummatory experience as a break in the continuity of experience. Likewise, achieving a new power of interaction with the environment through the reconstruction of habit is best understood as a pause, not a break in the process of growth. This is the point that Dewey later developed in his 1932 Ethics text, where he wrote, It is in the quality of becoming that virtue resides. We set up this and that end to be reached, but the end is growth itself. To make an end a final goal is but to arrest growth. 136 With this statement, Dewey wanted to show that character (his expression for motives or intentions) and conduct (acts) are inseparable because they are only different sides of habit formation, and consequently, growth. Therefore, Dewey argued that the habits produced by cognitive inquiry provide freedom to individuals insofar as they open up the possibility for new interpretations, whereas habits formed through repetition, i.e. tradition, restrict freedom and often become our masters by restricting growth. 135 DE, MW 9:46 136 LW 7:306 65

PAGE 70

If experience is the formation of context, and inquiry enriches that context, then growth could be seen as the outcome of context. In this sense, it is noteworthy that the term edification can be substituted for growth taken in the sense of habit acquisition, without a loss of meaning. It is common to refer to someone who has the refined habits concomitant with education as edified, and the relationship between this expression and the root it shares with edifice should not be overlooked. Those who have received an expansive education have built up their habits of interacting with their surroundings. Similarly, when a community permits individuals to grow, it will experience growth as well. Thus, it would seem that Deweys work on experience, inquiry, and growth illustrated the importance of context and offered us a rich and detailed understanding of culture. Pragmatic Method and Context One of Deweys most pressing concerns was that philosophy had become yet another tradition that arrested growth. Although most philosophical schools of thought employed empirical and critical methods, he saw the method of pragmatism as the only one that fostered growth through an orientation toward practicality. This is what led Dewey to devote so much time to the concepts of experience, inquiry, and growth. When empirical method is oriented in such a way, the active features of experience are highlighted and interaction becomes the most dependable model, which consequently blurs the distinction between the creature and its surroundings. When critical, or reflective, methods are pointed toward real world results, then inquiry takes on a decidedly experimental tone and the meaningfulness of actions 66

PAGE 71

becomes easier to account for. And, when these concepts are combined, it becomes obvious that the notion of self is a byproduct of the habits acquired by the practical import of these dealings with surroundings. Therefore, on Deweys view, the pragmatic method succeeds where other methods fail because it recognizes the importance of contexts and, when followed, can lead to a transformation of those contexts. Simply put, pragmatism makes philosophy relevant again; it gives it the power to affect its surroundings, whether natural or cultural, and Deweys version of pragmatic method offers a means of improving culture. First, his work on experience brought out its natural elements of interaction between organism and environment. We saw that, for him, experience is coterminous with context, and in a general sense, with culture itself. We also saw that experience is divisible into several modes, each with its own strategy for coping with the instability of the environment. Some of those modes, i.e. those which do not involve reflection, involve a type of coping that relies upon the principle of value. And, although these modes can provide the organism with helpful habits, the growth that derives from those habits is a spreading out, not a building up of culture. Context, in such an instance, is broad but it has no depth it is, in a word, superficial. One of the modes of experience, however, has proven to be successful in transforming indeterminacy, viz. the cognitive. When inquiry is made within this mode, cognitive habits are formed that can enrich the context. These habits provide the organism a chance to grow, and subsequently society and culture will grow as well. 67

PAGE 72

By emphasizing pragmatic method, which excels in the capacity to identify and transform context, Dewey provided philosophy a powerful tool in critiquing culture. One of Deweys most oft-quoted passages put it thusly, Philosophy recovers itself when it ceases to be a device for dealing with the problems of philosophers and becomes a method, cultivated by philosophers, for dealing with the problems of men. 137 And, although the intellectual climate in this country has changed dramatically in the eighty-odd years since Dewey penned those words, they seem just as appropriate now as they did when he wrote them. I submit that the rest of Deweys thought could be useful in revitalizing American intellectual life, since, on his view, the responsibility of the philosopher is to be just as concerned with public issues as with esoteric ones. Social hope, i.e. the hope for a free and peaceful society, is consistent with Deweyan contextualism and, thus, his might be the position philosophy will have to adopt if it seeks to ever plunge back into the realm of public affairs. 137 MW 10:46 68

PAGE 73

REFERENCES Anton, John P. American Naturalism and Greek Philosophy (Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books) 2005. Boisvert, Raymond. Deweys Metaphysics (New York: Fordham University Press) 1988. _______________.Forget Emerson, Forget Growth, Embrace Anaximander: Pragmatism and the Tragic Sense By Raymond D. Boisvert. Proceedings of the 2002 Society for the Advancement of American Philosophy Conference www.americanphilosophy.org/archives/2002_Conference/2002_papers/boisvert_saito.htm Mar. 6 th 2005. Dewey, John. The Collected Works of John Dewey, 1882-1953 37 volumes. Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1967-1987. Holmes, Oliver W. Holmes-Laski. Letters: The Correspondence of Mr. Justice Holmes and Harold J. Laski, 1916-1935, ed. Mark DeWolfe Howe (Cambridge: Harvard University Press) 1953. James, William. Pragmatism and Other Writings (New York: Penguin Classics) 2000. James, William. The Will to Believe and Other Essays in Popular Philosophy (San Raphael, CA.: Dover Publishing) 1956. Menand, Louis. The Metaphysical Club (New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux) 2001. Peirce, Charles. The Rules of Philosophy, from Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce ed. by Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss. (Cambridge: Harvard University Press) 1934. Schilpp, Paul & Hahn, Lewis. (eds.) The Philosophy of John Dewey: The Library of Living Philosophers, vol. 1. (Lasalle, IL: Open Court, 3 rd edition) 1989. Stuhr, John J. Pragmatism and Classical American Philosophy: Essential Readings and Interpretive Essays 2 nd ed. (Oxford: Oxford University Press) 2000. Talisse, Robert. On Dewey (Belmont, CA: Wadsworth) 1999. Wheelwright, Philip Ellis. Heraclitus. (New York: Oxford University Press) 1968.

PAGE 74

70 BIBLIOGRAPHY Eldridge, Michael. Transforming Experience. (Nashville, TN: Vanderbilt University Press) 1998. Gavin, William. In Deweys Wake. (New York: State University of New York Press) 2003. Gouinlock, James. The Moral Writings of John Dewey (Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books) 1994. Guignon, C. & Hiley, D. (eds.) Contemporary Philosophy In Focus: Richard Rorty (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press) 2003. Putnam, Ruth Anna. The Cambridge Companion to William James (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press) 1997. Smith, John. The Spirit of American Philosophy (New York: Oxford University Press) 1966.