USF Libraries
USF Digital Collections

A philosophical inquiry on the valuation and selection of musical materials for culturally diverse learners in global en...

MISSING IMAGE

Material Information

Title:
A philosophical inquiry on the valuation and selection of musical materials for culturally diverse learners in global environments
Physical Description:
Book
Language:
English
Creator:
Bassett, Jonathan
Publisher:
University of South Florida
Place of Publication:
Tampa, Fla
Publication Date:

Subjects

Subjects / Keywords:
Postmodernism
Multiculturalism
Value
Diversity
Education
Western
Aesthetic
Quality
Inclusion
Dissertations, Academic -- Music -- Doctoral -- USF   ( lcsh )
Genre:
non-fiction   ( marcgt )

Notes

Abstract:
ABSTRACT: The selection of musical materials for use in the classroom is problematic. Since music educators have limited time with students, the inclusion of musical materials necessitates the perceived exclusion of other musical materials. This perception is due in part to the increasing diversity of students represented in the classroom, the cultural labeling of musical materials, the influence of multiculturalism on music education, and the influence of the Western aesthetic in music education. Since diverse groups can and do propose socially perceived valuations of these materials as critical for the inclusion of specific musical materials for use in the classroom, this inquiry examines some of the problems associated with the perceived valuations of musical materials for students. As multiple musical materials are used toward similar educational outcomes, or a single musical material is used toward diverse educational outcomes, the value of musical materials is determined by their perceived function for the individual, the group, and the universal human. These valuations are connected to ideologies that sometimes conflict with one another. Numerous solutions to these conflicts in diverse student populations are not perfect, but necessary. Considerations of similar characteristics of perceived musical quality within and across cultures provide an approach to one possible solution. Music educators should be better equipped to make appropriate decisions as they choose musical materials for use in the classroom when consideration is given to the diverse perceptions of these materials around the world and the historical and socio-political frameworks that describe what music education should be.
Thesis:
Dissertation (Ph.D.)--University of South Florida, 2010.
Bibliography:
Includes bibliographical references.
System Details:
Mode of access: World Wide Web.
System Details:
System requirements: World Wide Web browser and PDF reader.
Statement of Responsibility:
by Jonathan Bassett.
General Note:
Title from PDF of title page.
General Note:
Document formatted into pages; contains X pages.
General Note:
Includes vita.

Record Information

Source Institution:
University of South Florida Library
Holding Location:
University of South Florida
Rights Management:
All applicable rights reserved by the source institution and holding location.
Resource Identifier:
usfldc doi - E14-SFE0003471
usfldc handle - e14.3471
System ID:
SFS0027786:00001


This item is only available as the following downloads:


Full Text
xml version 1.0 encoding UTF-8 standalone no
record xmlns http:www.loc.govMARC21slim xmlns:xsi http:www.w3.org2001XMLSchema-instance xsi:schemaLocation http:www.loc.govstandardsmarcxmlschemaMARC21slim.xsd
leader nam 22 Ka 4500
controlfield tag 007 cr-bnu---uuuuu
008 s2010 flu s 000 0 eng d
datafield ind1 8 ind2 024
subfield code a E14-SFE0003471
035
(OCoLC)
040
FHM
c FHM
049
FHMM
090
XX9999 (Online)
1 100
Bassett, Jonathan.
0 245
A philosophical inquiry on the valuation and selection of musical materials for culturally diverse learners in global environments
h [electronic resource] /
by Jonathan Bassett.
260
[Tampa, Fla] :
b University of South Florida,
2010.
500
Title from PDF of title page.
Document formatted into pages; contains X pages.
Includes vita.
502
Dissertation (Ph.D.)--University of South Florida, 2010.
504
Includes bibliographical references.
516
Text (Electronic dissertation) in PDF format.
538
Mode of access: World Wide Web.
System requirements: World Wide Web browser and PDF reader.
3 520
ABSTRACT: The selection of musical materials for use in the classroom is problematic. Since music educators have limited time with students, the inclusion of musical materials necessitates the perceived exclusion of other musical materials. This perception is due in part to the increasing diversity of students represented in the classroom, the cultural labeling of musical materials, the influence of multiculturalism on music education, and the influence of the Western aesthetic in music education. Since diverse groups can and do propose socially perceived valuations of these materials as critical for the inclusion of specific musical materials for use in the classroom, this inquiry examines some of the problems associated with the perceived valuations of musical materials for students. As multiple musical materials are used toward similar educational outcomes, or a single musical material is used toward diverse educational outcomes, the value of musical materials is determined by their perceived function for the individual, the group, and the universal human. These valuations are connected to ideologies that sometimes conflict with one another. Numerous solutions to these conflicts in diverse student populations are not perfect, but necessary. Considerations of similar characteristics of perceived musical quality within and across cultures provide an approach to one possible solution. Music educators should be better equipped to make appropriate decisions as they choose musical materials for use in the classroom when consideration is given to the diverse perceptions of these materials around the world and the historical and socio-political frameworks that describe what music education should be.
590
Advisor: C. Victor Fung, Ph.D.
653
Postmodernism
Multiculturalism
Value
Diversity
Education
Western
Aesthetic
Quality
Inclusion
690
Dissertations, Academic
z USF
x Music
Doctoral.
773
t USF Electronic Theses and Dissertations.
4 856
u http://digital.lib.usf.edu/?e14.3471



PAGE 1

A Philosophical I nquiry on the V aluation and S election of M usical M aterials for C ulturally D iverse L earners in G lobal E nvironments b y Jonathan Bassett A dissertation s ubmitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy School of Music College of T he Arts University of South Florida Major Professor: C. Victor Fung, Ph.D. David A. Williams, Ph.D. Carolyn Stuart, D M A Stephen Turner, Ph.D. Date of Approval: April 5 th 2010 Keywords: postmodernism, multiculturalism, value, diversity, education W estern, aesthetic quality, inclusion Copyright 2010, Jonathan Bassett

PAGE 2

For Jenny, Drew, Aden, and Anna For Victor and his beautiful new baby that will be here soon For Carolyn and her beautiful new baby that is already here. Of making many books there is no end, and much study is wearisome to the flesh. Ecclesiastes 12:12

PAGE 3

i Table of Contents ABSTRACT ................................ ................................ ................................ ....................... iii Chapter 1 Introduction ................................ ................................ ................................ ........ 1 Brief Hist ory ................................ ................................ ................................ ........... 2 Contextualizing the Problem ................................ ................................ ................... 6 Addressing the Problem ................................ ................................ .......................... 9 Method ................................ ................................ ................................ .................. 11 Chapter 2 Contextualizing Inclusion and Exclusion ................................ ......................... 13 The Problem of Labeling Musical Materials ................................ ........................ 14 The Problem of Classification Labels ................................ ................................ ... 16 The Problem of Consumerism ................................ ................................ .............. 19 The Problem of Social Diversity ................................ ................................ ........... 21 Summary ................................ ................................ ................................ ............... 22 Chapter 3 Postmodernism, Multiculturalism, and Musical Materials .............................. 25 Postmodernism ................................ ................................ ................................ ...... 26 Globalism ................................ ................................ ................................ .............. 28 Multiculturalism ................................ ................................ ................................ .... 29 Philosophical challenges to postmodern arguments ................................ ............. 32 Music Education and Multiculturalism ................................ ................................ 38 Social Justice ................................ ................................ ................................ ......... 40 Summary ................................ ................................ ................................ ............... 45

PAGE 4

ii Chapter 4 Philosophical Perspective of Musical Value ................................ .................... 46 Individual Value ................................ ................................ ................................ .... 49 Cultural ................................ ................................ ................................ ................. 54 Universal Value ................................ ................................ ................................ .... 61 Summary ................................ ................................ ................................ ............... 62 Chapter 5 Some Comparisons of Current Strategies ................................ ........................ 64 Bennett Reimer ................................ ................................ ................................ ..... 64 Elliott ................................ ................................ ................................ ..................... 72 Jorgensen ................................ ................................ ................................ ............... 74 Additional Texts ................................ ................................ ................................ .... 78 Summary ................................ ................................ ................................ ............... 79 Chapter 6 Quality of Musical Materials ................................ ................................ ............ 80 Quality of Materials ................................ ................................ .............................. 83 Meaning ................................ ................................ ................................ ................ 90 Summary ................................ ................................ ................................ ............... 93 Chapter 7 Conclusion ................................ ................................ ................................ ........ 95 Valuation of Musical Materials in the United States ................................ ............ 96 Valuations as Conflicting Ideologies ................................ ................................ .. 100 Decision ................................ ................................ ................................ .............. 106 Solutions ................................ ................................ ................................ ............. 112 References ................................ ................................ ................................ ....................... 116 About the Author ................................ ................................ ................................ ... End Page

PAGE 5

iii A Philosophical Inquiry on the V aluation and S election of M usical M aterials for C ulturally D iverse L earners in G lobal E nvironments ABSTRACT The selection of musical materials for use in the classroom is problematic. Since music educators have limited time with students the inclusion of musical materials necessitates the perceived exclusion of other musical materials. This perception is due in part to the increasing diversity of students represented in the classroom, the cultural labeling of musical materials, the influence of multiculturalism on music education, and the influence of the Western aesthetic in music education. Since diverse group s can and do propose socially perceived valuations of these materials as critical for the inclusion of specific musical materials for use in the classroom, this inquiry examine s some of t he problems associated with the perceived valuations of musical mater ials for students. As m ultiple musical materials are used toward similar educational outcomes, or a single musical material is used toward divers e educational outcomes, the value of musical materials is determined by their perceived function for the individual, the group, and the universal human. These valuations are connected to ideologies that sometimes conflict with one another. Numerous s olutions to these conflicts in diverse student populations are not perfect, but necessary. Considerations of similar characteristics of perceived musical quality within and across cultures provide an approach to one possible solution. Music educators should be better equipped to make appropriate decisions as they choo se musical materials for use in the classroom when consideration is given to the diverse

PAGE 6

iv perceptions of these materials around t he world and the historical and socio political frameworks that describe what music education should be.

PAGE 7

1 Chapter 1 Introduction A variety of philosophical frameworks is available for the selection of musical materials for use in the classroom. Depending on the diversity of educational goals of communities, schools, and teachers, musical materials are selected for use a ccording to how well these materials are perceived to be situated within these goals. Over the last few decades, the nature of these musical goals has become more and more diverse as the needs and desires of students expand (Jorgensen, 2003). As music educ ators strive appropriately to adapt, past assumptions about music education are revisited, revised, rejected, and even resurrected as new assumptions are woven into the existing r the diverse populations they serve (Jorgensen, 2003, p. 3). Thus, music education, like other disciplines, seeks to reconsider past assumptions as it moves toward cultural rather than universal (or m odern, or Western) perceptions Further complicating th e issue of what to do within music education is the stability of music programs. As music programs are marginalized in public school curriculums across the country, it becomes essential for music educators to advocate music education to their schools and c ommunities. Bennett Reimer, a leading advocate because of our limited vision of what proper music education consists of we have become progressively more irrelevant . (2007 p. 3 ). The issue of relevance has led some music educators to challenge current practices in music education. For many, defending the need for their programs has become essential

PAGE 8

2 for survival, even to the point of questioning and rethinking traditional practic es in music education that are perceived to no longer serve the needs of students, or the needs of too few students (see Williams, 2007). The overwhelming presence of music in diverse cultures suggests that humans place high value on musical experiences. The question that remains is related to the nature of these values. According to Gardiner (2003), music has the ability to direct us creational activity, and assessment o music are dependent on how we choose to interact with music, and for what purposes. In order to advocate for music education, it becomes necessary then, to find firm footing in order to answer the fu ndamental question of what music is for (Sloboda, 2001). unique characteristics of ways to know and ways to be intelligent, that music be offered to all children if they a p. 5). It i s these unique characteristics that will need to find broad acceptance between music educators, students, administrators, communities, and the diverse cultures they represent if music education is to thrive in contemporary society. The philosophical bases for the selection of musical materials for use in the classroom are fundamental ly reflective of how educators are measuring the value of music and music education. Brief History In the 19th century, the mora l development of the individual took precedence Popular music, folk music, and artistic music of the time were not readily applied in music education. Instead, songs promoting nationalism and devotion were considered to

PAGE 9

3 be important. After studying the te achings of Swiss teacher Johann Pestalozzi, Lowell Mason incorporated rote singing and teaching musical materials sequentially. In addition, Ma son successfully commercialized his own musical materials for music educators, creating both supply and demand fo r musical materials (Mark & Gary, 1999). In the secondary schools, the vocal music curriculum focused on music composed primarily by Western composers, and incorporated texts such as the High School Choralist (1866) and (1872). A round the turn of the c entury, interest in music appreciation for classical musi c was encouraged by facilitating the opportunity for high school students to attend classical concerts. The educational value of these concerts for these students was considere d as a kind of training for listeners. School orchestras did not begin to appear substantially in the United States until the turn of the century. The popularity of touring bands and orchestras after the civil war eventually led to the extracurricular high school orchestra. Elementary orchestras soon followed (Mark & Gary, 1999). The subject of musical materials d id not become a significantly debated topic in music education until the Yale Seminar on Music Education at Yale University in 1963, where the primary issues of importance were musical materials and music performance. large body of authentic and meaningful music to augment and enrich the rep ertory p. 345). What emerged was a list of over 400 compositions from the traditional cannon of Western classical music, as well as some folk music. However, it was not embraced by music educators N ot all educators were in agreement about what music education should

PAGE 10

4 become. This became more apparent during the 19 60 s, 19 70 s, and 19 80 s, when rapid changes in American society left education in general scrambling to keep up (Mark & Gary, 1999 ). In 1958, the National Society for the Study of Education published the Ba sic Concepts in Music Education, a collection of essays that attempted to lay the groundwork for a philosophy of music education. Several influential writers supported the idea tha t teaching music for its own value would be critical for student enrichment, and the concept of aesthetic education was born as a tool for advocacy. Along with aesthetic education, the idea of conceptual learning developed, and a wide range of methods for teaching music emerged, including the methods of Dalcroze, Orff, Suzuki, and Kodly. It is during this time that many new musical materials were also legitimized as a part of the curriculum, including jazz and popular music. Their legitimacy was supported by the Tanglewood Symposium, in which participants agreed that the development of a musical hierarchy was impossible as well as inappropriate in that the concept of musical hierarchy promoted class barriers. This further opened the door for all types of mu sic to be incorporated into the curriculum, including rock, electronic, and world musics (Mark & Gary, 1999). The selection of musical materials for the classroom has been a source of contention for music educators, especially over the past 50 years. The Yale seminar of 1963 addressed some of the problems with the music materials being utilized in the Mark & Gary,

PAGE 11

5 1999, p p 12). These contentions are stil l alive for some. Glidden (2009) states: I am sorry to report that from my observation, we have lost ground s ince the Yale Seminar of 1963, the report of which intrigued me to the point of passion about the prospect of teaching the literature of music in schools on a par with teaching the literature of the language. This statement reflects a general dissatisfacti on with the selection of music al materials over time, generally shared by all concer ned, although offering different reasons for championing diverse materials. Music education in the United States today reflects a complex and diverse mixture of traditions, cultures, and commercial consumerism (Mark & Gary, 1999). From its inclusion in 19 th century public school classrooms utilizing materials as tools for the m oral development of the student, American music educatio n has been transformed toward a representation of the desires of the global community, including everything from gospel choirs and marching bands to music technology and world music courses. However, this transformation has not made a clean break from past traditions and cultures in order to replace them with newer and seemingly more relevant ideas. Christopher Small argued t Renaissance We stern tradition p. 207 ). Instead, the transformation is perhaps better illustrated as a snowball gathering new music materials from diverse cultures without ever getting rid of the old ones. In addition, technology has made the utilization of globa l musical materials more accessible and the construction of musical materials more rapid and user friendly. As a consequence, musical materials available for use in music education are now as vast as they are diverse.

PAGE 12

6 W hile music education advocacy has ga ined some ground through the efforts of organizations like MENC, including the creation of the National Standards in Music (see Reimer, 2005) and a resolution in congress outlining the importance of music education in 2007 ( A m e r i c a n M u s i c C o n f e r e n c e 2007) there is little consensus among music educators supporting a particular philosophy of music education (Mark & Gary, 1999). Music education in the United States faces a peculiar crisis in that very few high school students participate in music classes Re imer (2007) suggests this number to be som ewhere between 9 and 12 percent Perhaps one of the strongest arguments against the role of traditional materials in music education is that it is simply unjustifiable because so few students actually listen to or participate in it. Reimer (2005) stated what teachers consider musically valuable and what students/communities regard as such p. 248). He continued to argue that current practices based in Western clas sical tradition were a probl em that needed to be addressed, citing a p. 249). While his point was well made, the potential value of traditional materials for all American students was somewhat compromised by this statement, outlining the need to further examine how musical materials were perceived by all concerned. Contextualizing the Problem In orde r to contextual ize the philosophical bases for including or excluding musical materials in the music curriculum, it is important to consider that these arguments are rooted in broader philosophies of current practices in diverse social structures. These ph ilosophies are as diverse as styles of music, but many are centered

PAGE 13

7 around diverse cultural and intercultural perspectives. These perspectives range from aesthetic philosophy of synergism between diverse philosophies in music education to p osition papers that highlight the importance of countering social power structures through non traditional strategies and materials in music education (e.g. Jaffurs, 2004). The problem s related to the aesthetic and social valu ations of music are found th roughout music education research literature. For example, Regelski (2005) suggests that praxialism, rather than aesthetics, can provide the perceived social value necessary for promoting music education. Still other emerging philosophi es involving social identit y (e.g. Hargreaves & Marshall, 2003) and perceived musical meaning through group interaction with particular musical styles serve to add more perspectives for consideration in the music curriculum. These philosophies (and others) often consider tra ditional practices involving classical music materials to be out of touch with student interests and creative potential. Jorgensen (1997) perhaps offers a more sympathetic ly and p. 36). The most obvious example of the perceived conflicts between musical materials in the literature involves the role of Western classical m usic. Jorgensen (1997) described how o ne of the traditional (and highly controversial) arguments for Western classical musical materials holds that the evolutionary process of music composition is a p. 43 ). T his stance is in turn, challenged by the complex, non linear progression of music throughout history, the difficulty in evaluating the quality of music out of its social context, and the

PAGE 14

8 presence of other types of musics that rival the complexity of W estern classical music (Jorgensen, 1997). The acceleration of cultural change through increased technologies and globalization has also presented a range of new challenges for current practices in music education. For Jorgensen (1997), t he prevailing musical considerations include formal vs. contextual analysis of musical works, the hierarchy of musical traditions, transmitting historical wisdom vs. transforming social structures, contextual interaction with music vs. continuity (life lon g learning), making and receiving music, and musical understanding vs. pleasure. Additionally, assuming the music educator has adopted a philosophy of his or her own, the gulf between theory and practice presents yet another set of problems. Jorgensen (199 7) contends: Although educators, among them musicians, have sought the high road to musical understanding, it is unlikely that such a way is possible. Rather, music educators may need to be content with admitting a variety of ways in which people come to k now music. It is unlikely that any practice can ever be based on any one coherent set of assumptions or that any one set of assumptions constitutes a philosophy or theory capable of only one set of concomitant practices ( p. 90) Sloboda (2001) also highli ghts the importance of realizing the various ways in which we interact with music: Music education in schools cannot function effectively without an implicit agreement between stakeholders (e.g. teachers, student, parents, government etc.) about what it is for. of the discourses of these diverse groups . ( p. 249)

PAGE 15

9 He identifies seven cultural trends (multiculturalism, youth culture, electronic communication, feminism, secularism, niche cultures, and postmodernism) that have moved the focus of music education away from the traditional foundation of studying classical artworks, and suggests that current practices in music education are insufficiently effective in meeting the needs of students. Ad ditionally, Jorgensen (1996) identifies the problematic nature of artistic values and cultural significance, and how these can affect music education philosophy: Searching for musical value, for example, may emphasize the sophisticated classical musics; in terrelating music with common, everyday life may emphasize the more accessible folk and popular musics ( p. 6) But these philosophical challenges are not new. Jorgensen (1996) points out that Aristotle acknowledged difficulty justifying the arts in that they existed without significant purpose, while Plato viewed the arts as a Jorgensen, 1996, p. 1). Her solution for justifying the arts in general education is to addre ss the challenges to the vulnerabilities of the diverse philosop hical bases of music education. These diverse bases are reflected in how music educators select material s for use in the classroom Addressing the Problem In the classroom, this collection of diverse music al materials is too broad to represent in the allotted time, and educators choose not only the materials they will use, but continually exercise the philosophical criteria for the selection of those materials. Inherent in each selection of th ese musical materials is the fundamental question of what the music is for allowing for the possibility of one musical material to function toward a

PAGE 16

10 variety of philosophical ends. However, some of these ends come in conflict with one another, making the s election of musical materials for the classroom not only a question of what to include, but what to exclude. As such, the nature of selecting m usical materials is problematic, and becomes more so as the diversity of the students increases. Philosophical b ases of music education that address these and other problems are almost as numerous as the music materials they represent. Bennett Reimer, Christopher Small, Estelle Jorgensen, David Elliott, and numerous others have produced a wealth of literature addres sing no t only diverse problems in the philosophy of music and music education, but by providing potential solutions for these problems within social contexts, including the role of music education in considering issues related to diversity and social justi ce. Consequently, music education has become a source of promoting an increasingly wide number of cultural groups. These groups include cultures categorized by socioeconomic status, geography, race, gender, or even sexual orientation. Each of these uniquel y defined groups expresses interest in the promotion or preservation of particular types of music materials of communal interest (Elliott, 2007). Inevitably, some groups have expressed a disinterest in (or even objection to) other musical materials that do not reflect the values of their culture. Music education, on the other hand, has traditionally (Reimer, 2007, p. 21). It is a problem that deserves a closer look to deter mine how these objections are warranted, and in what contexts. Before continuing, however, it is important to note that theoretical frameworks for musical meaning and value are not being overlooked. In general, it i s assumed that the reader considers that musical materials are theoretically not (sound) objects, but

PAGE 17

11 constructs that operate individually within cultures (i.e. Fiske, 1996 ; Elliott, 1995 ), and what I contend to be constructs that may operate individually among cultures. For the purpose of this discussion, musical materials (sheet music, recordings, concerts, composing, improvising, and all other performance modes and mediums in action ) are treated as objects and/or actions that are considered to be musical with in and among cultures Musical materials are chosen for use in the classroom to promote various perceived valuations of these materials by perform ing or listening to them. I t b e c o m e s apparent that there is further disagreement about what th e value of music is both within and among cultures, which complicates arguments pertaining to what music is for Method The method for this philosophical inquiry is primarily synopsis and analysis ( Jorgensen 1992), and is limited by its holistic and sele ctive approach to a large and redundant body of literature. However, this approach is valuable in that the arguments related to the selection of musical materials are often narrowly focused and discussed without contextual sympathy, or they are discussed w ithout sufficient consideration of the problems associated with each position (Reimer, 2005). Polarized literature has been selected at times to make these limitations more obvious. In addition, the inquiry is focused exclusively on Western philosophical bases of music education, and does not purposely include considerations from non Western philosophical foundations This inquiry is intended to assist the all music teacher s develop a more comprehensive phil osophical approach in the selection of musical materials for use in the classroom. As such, it is important to lay out a framework for discussion. In Chapter 2 the role of musical materials as they relate to problems of inclusion and exclusion for

PAGE 18

12 diverse groups is discussed. Chapter 3 address es the problem of groups be ing contextualized within the postmodern framework of multiculturalism and social justice. The third part of the inquiry (Chapter 4) consider s philosophical perspectives of valuing musical m aterials from the perspectives of the individual, the group, and the universal. Chapter 5 examine s strategies for the selection of musical materials as they relate to the philosophical perspectives of Bennett Reimer, Estelle Jorgensen, and David Elliott F inally, a discussion of musical materials as they relate to perspectives of musical quality is presented in Chapter 6 and Chapter 7 summarize s the arguments by tying together the various perspectives associated with musical materials in order to achieve greater contextual understanding of the problems in the hopes of moving toward their eventual solutions. Practical suggestions for future practices of inclusi on and exclusion of musical materials in the classroom are presented If comprehensive music education is a goal, then music educators need to find greater agreement about what materials are appropriate for use in the classroom. This inquiry is designed to move toward a better understanding on how cultural and musical criteria are valued as factors for the selection of musical materials.

PAGE 19

13 Chapter 2 Contextualizing I nclusion and E xclusion In the past, my own thoughts as an ensemble director when considering musical materials for inclusion or exclusion in the classroom were always related to the quality of the material itself. Or, I might pick a piece to perform because it fit well into a diverse program. But the word diverse to me generally m eant allegro vs. adagio, Renaissance vs. Romantic, or some textural or performance occasion consideration. I did not typically include a piece because it was from a particular region, or because it represented a particular group, even though I did include many works considered to be culturally diverse for those reasons. For music educators, relying on past assumptions about materials is problematic, especially those assumptions rooted in Western mus ical frameworks However, current assumptions about musical materials are also problematic. Diverse labeling, rising commercial consumerism, and increasing social diversity have influenced student interest in musical materials. These and numerous other con siderations affect the way students interact with materials in the classroom, and each perspective presents new challenges to the selection of musical materials. Perhaps a reasonable approach can be made toward developing a greater understanding of the div erse criteria appropriate to the selection of musical materials by considering the problematic nature of labels as they are perceived to be socially charged in some way. Labels sometimes make the conversation about musical materials more difficult, and cr eate consternation where it is more often than not counterproductive.

PAGE 20

14 The P roblem of L abeling M usical M aterials The diverse categorizations of musical materials are valuable in the facilitation of the diverse utilizations of musical materials. Unfortunate ly, the use of cultural labels can be perceived as somewhat problematic in music education. In the culturally diverse classrooms of the United States, the inclusion of the music of one culture ( or group ) would seem to make necessary the inclusion of all cu ltural musics unless some other label is shown to be more appropriate. Consider for instance, the calculated use of labels in the current political climate in the United States. President Barak Obama has been carefully labeled as the first black presiden t (even though his mother is white ) which suits the desires of the society towards concepts of social equality based on the injustices of the past. Additionally, the first Latino woman Supreme Court justice was sworn into office, similarly representative of J oe Biden need not be labeled as a white male Rather, it is understood that Mr. Biden belongs to the historically dominant culture, and the labels are not conducive to supporting societal strides toward social justice (see Small, 1996; Greene, 1988). Perha ps many better examples could be drawn, but the immediate concern is the understanding that labels are used not only as descriptors, but as tools toward social and political objectives (Reimer, 2005). It would then likewise be appropriate to consider that if educators decide to study and perform the music of China (monumen tally diverse in its own right) they should consider whether or not to also include the music of every other country as well, using

PAGE 21

15 socio political and geographical criteria as the central criteria for labeling music. The same could be said utilizing other descriptive, socially stratified labels for the incorporation of a w ide variety of popular musics in the classroom ( i.e., if one includes rock, one should include country and Broadway as well). It becomes obvious here that there are too many musical materials, categorizations, and cultures to allow adequate representation of each in music education in order to obtain equitable representation. Once the teacher has selected the musical mater ial for use in the classroom, all other materials have essentially been excluded. If the teacher does not have a clear set of criteria for determining the inclusion of musical materials in the classroom, realizing the social attachments to each, these sele ctions can be perceived to imply cultural inequity, even when it is not intended. Additionally, by labeling music as belonging to or the product of one particular group of people over another, the distinction between we and them becomes significant enough to warrant conversation about whose music is includ ed in the classroom, rather than what music is included in the classroom. As American classrooms become more d iverse conflicts around the selection of musical materials are less avoidable. Inevitably, so me group will be underrepresented by the materials presented in the classroom, and the dominant culture is perceived as being either irrelevant to or imposed upon the unwilling ( e.g., religious texts in choral music). In the search for relevant materia ls, the criteria for relevance are not necessarily shared by all involved. As a result, music is categorized, classified, or otherwise labeled according to dissimilar criteria. These labels, while necessary, create diverse problems for educators.

PAGE 22

16 The Problem of Classification Labels The labeling of music is necessary in that it helps individuals sort through the multitude of musical materials available for consumption. Each label provides information about the material it categorizes, and allows it to be eva luated by the listener before actually listening to it. On the internet, websites like iTunes allow individuals to search general keywords like rock or classical and their subcategories. Online retailers, like Amazon help consumers by listing similar item s purchased by others who have purchased the album under consideration. By doing so, even without a specific musical label, consumers are grouped by their purchasing habits. Research in music al taste and preference divides individuals into groups based on a variety of criteria, ranging from socio economic status to illegal drug use, thus labeling the listener along with the material in order to examine social or cultural correlations ( e.g., Hargreaves & North, 2007 ). Music can also be categorized by the mu perspective of the music in action rather than the traditionally defining characteristics of th e musical materials themselves. For example one study by Kim and Belkin (2002) asked 22 non music experts to write words they would use to descri be or search the internet for the music samples they were asked to listen to. The researchers then grouped like terms, resulting in seven categorical approaches to descriptions of musical materials. Among the most frequently util ized categories were emotio ns nature occasions and neutral concepts Musical features were not utilized as frequently, and represented only 4% of the descriptions and 13% of the search terms. In every instance, the re sult of these categorizations helps to explain what the music i s for from the views of the consumer. In music education, the labeling of musical materials also takes place, although

PAGE 23

17 emphasis may be placed on a different and uniquely inclusive set of criteria. For instance, in secondary music education in the United States, choral music can be inclusive of everything from a Bach chorale to a Michael Jackson pop arrangement. In traditional large ensembles, the performance medium alone generally provide s the categorization criteria. A high school orchestra performs orch estral literature, which on the whole means nothing more than music writt en or arranged for an orchestra These overwhelmingly inclusive labels for music categories are used primarily to facilitate the ensemble they are designed for rather than the stylist ic preference of the student or the audience. A curious side effect of these broad types of categorizations of musical materials is the implied assumption that all of these materials are equally valuable for students, audiences, or toward some educational end, not to mention the assumption that the ensemble itself as a medium is valuable. O ther categorizations of musical materials presume similar values via a different set of criteria. In the last few decades, prominent attention has been given to diverse musical cultures within a geographically, ethnically, or ideologically unique group of people. These categorizations (similar to studies in taste and preference) are more oriented toward social behaviors than the study of the musical material itself. One of the main goals of listening to these works is to develop an appreciation for or understanding of the cultures that produce the music. As t he music appreciation movement of West ern classica l music in the middle of the 20 th century in music education celebrated musical works of perceived significance the celebration of diversity of musical materials has become conversely more important than the perceived musical val ue of the mate rials.

PAGE 24

18 Still other labels are applied to help put music materials into categories. Among music educators, musical descriptions include adjectives pertaining to positive and negative perspectives of musical value relevance, or quality Music from this pe rspective can be seen in terms of releva nce and can include terms such as esoteric or authentic These labels are useful in providing a way of describing the value of the music for society within a socio political framework. T he music materials are sorted according to the role they play within a diverse and economically stratified population like the United States. These labels indicate some social agenda or role whether pos itively or negatively perceived for the musical materials under consideration. Additionally, t he concept of music as an aesthetic art object is often contrasted with the concept of music as an aesthetic art action (e.g., Elliot t 1995; Small, 1996), emphasizing the importance of the social relationship between musician and audience. These culturally understood musical relationships are valued within the structure of age old aesthetic topics of form, practice, and cultural context in the direction of that aspect of context h aving to do with social justice p. 53). The valuation of musical materials from these perspectives becomes somewhat problematic Perhaps there are numerous additional criteria for labeling musical materials that hav e not been mentioned, but the point has been made clear that there are multiple ways to describe musical materials, including evaluative assessments (utilizing diverse criteria) by individuals and groups. The presence of these labels provides the opportuni ty to discuss how perceptions of culturally implied (geographical, historical, or philosophical) ownership of musical materials (i.e. Western classical Indian, hip hop, etc.), creat i n g

PAGE 25

19 problems for music educators in the classroom as they select materials As a consequence of these and other categorizations, the selection of some musical materials instead of other musical materials at least implies value judgments The Problem of Consumerism The problem of labeling music is further complicated by consume r culture, where personal taste and group preferences are inseparable from the musical products that seemingly permeate every waking moment of the lives of contemporary students, regardless of their cultural orientation Jorgensen (2003) contends that lar culture in all of its forms sold by the media so silences other forms of musical expression that p. xi). Hence, c onsumer culture provides yet another set of criteria for educators to consider when choosing musical materials for use in the classroom. Should the music teacher seek to provide more opportunities to explore current trends in popular music? What materials should be rejected to accommodate these currently relevant materials? More importantly, to what end and for whom are these materials useful? It is necessary to consider the problems that stem from these questions. Christopher Small outlines the problems i nherent in even asking such questions as these : questions conceived in traditions of Western music education involving p. 149). For example, he describes the efforts of John Cage to resist earli er concepts of form in favor of promoting the act of making art. In essence, effort is made to perceive of Western music appropriately, according to a set of philosophical criteria. Small (1996) states: Art remains a commodity whose production remains in t he hands of experts, which we purchase when we feel the need of it, and in whose making we have no

PAGE 26

20 more hand than we have in the manufacture of our breakfast cereal. We can perceive not that a true regeneration of western music, and western society, can co me only when we can restore the power of creation to each individual in our society ( p. 166) O b v i o u s l y the author has a clear vision for what music is for, and continues to make a compelling case for the im portance of creativity. The purpose for the discus sion of this brief example is not to argue the value of creativity, but to assess the valuation of creativity that is assumed to be the proper one according to Small The valuation and definition of creativity i ts elf ( see Csikszentmihalyi, 1996 ) is situate d within the process of selecting musical materials for u se in the classroom as a function of music education. Our culture helps us make decisions about how we value creativity, and what creativity is within music education. These decisions are influenced by consumer culture. The c onsumer culture has been criticized by many philosophers Among them, Horkheimer and Adorno (2002) describe the deception of choice as seen in the categorization and labeling of the consumer rather than choice being representative of any real differences in art. At the same time, American e ducators are very interested in the desires of their students, which validate these choices as being signif icant precisely in terms of their differences as seen in the selection of musical materials for consumption. Thus, consumer culture is wrapped in issues related to culture, and it is difficult if not impossible, to isolate one from the other for considera tion. Simply put, it is problematic to value the utilization of musical materials for students based on what they consume on a regular basis.

PAGE 27

21 The Problem of Social Diversity In contemporary society, diversity itself is difficult to categorize. The musical interests of students are not only infinitely diverse, but fluid, and students quickly immerse themselves in one type of music after another. With an array of music available and easily accessible, sometimes the obscurity of a musical material may be its primary criteria for valuation. At other times, trends and friends are responsible for more choices regarding the selection of musical materials than the individual (see Hargreaves & North, 1997) As such, these musical activities are indeed primarily soci al in nature, and have very little to do with considerations of the music al material itself, instead of relying on the perceived value of the music as it supports the current social objective for the student A multicultural perspective in its global context understands unity in terms of equality among diverse groups. As such, issues of social justice have become a critical part of any field of study and the criteria for making musical decisions are cultural ra ther than musical, leaving other approaches to music evaluation to play a secondary role dependent entirely on the cultural perspective for its significance in the lives of individuals. Additionally, the Western philosophies of the aesthetic properties of musical materials (see Small, 1996) are deemphasized in favor of issues of social justice and equality, even though they are not in opposition outside of their elitist associations. Or, these traditional musics are considered to be irrelevant in contempor ary culture, citing the diversity of culture over time. Rather than understanding the musical materials utilized in traditional ensembles in classrooms in the United States as no longer being relevant, it may be more appropriate to say that the culture co llectively has decided to make them irrelevant whether by

PAGE 28

22 informed choice or ignorant indifference to some greater end. Many views of music educators are based on socio political beliefs, and reflect concepts related to the ideal society. Unfortunately, mu sical materials or perspectives that do not coincide with these views are contextualized as relevant or not based on these views. The goal here is not to vilify the se decision s of relevance and the multiplicity of variables associated with them but rather to protect any inappropriately attached music materials from being thrown out unnecessarily in order to promote inclusion of other musical materials In order to attract more diverse students to music education, t he justified move toward the education of the music afficianado ( Reimer, 2005) has gained ground in the literature primarily through the socio political ide ologies of contemporary thought ( e.g., ; Greene, 1988; Jorgensen 2 003 ; Small, 1996 ) citing a battle Small, 1996, p. 214). Whether or not this ironically romantic view of the struggle in music education is accurate may be critical to the evolution of the parameters educa tors utilize to construct t he music education curriculum. Multiculturalism addresses these and other issues related to social diversity, and is discussed in more detail in the next chapter. Summary In order to better promote music education and improve co mmunication between educators, students, and the communities in which they share musical experiences, the problematic nature of the diverse labels assigned to materials needs to be addressed. es, especially since they serve an increasingly diverse constituency, and society expects more of its schools than p. 3). While cultural, historic, stylis tic, and geographic labels of musical

PAGE 29

23 materials are valuable, they alone are inadequate to promote music itself as a viable part of the curriculum within diverse groups who have differing socio political views. While celebrating diversity is valued by many as a postmodern approach in education in general, it s application continues to be probl ematic among diverse disciplines in the Western culture. Nevertheless, some method of choosing musical materials for use in the classroom is needed to make sure groups are not excluded because of the nature of the musical materials being utilized. Perhaps it is better to reconsider the diverse applications of music in the collective human experience (both current and historical) rather than focusing entirely on the geographic and socio political diversity of musical materials within and among groups. This is not possible unless the criterion for the labeling and valuation of musical materials enjoys greater acceptance among educators, students, audiences, and professionals. Additionally, a better understanding is needed of the value of commercial music, fol k music, and art music materials available for use in the classroom. In order to move toward these objectives, it is important to reevaluate the ideological and socio political goals of music educators, and then use these goals as a framework for the appli cation of musical materials in the classroom by developing a more comprehensive approach to the selection of music materials for use in the classroom. To support a framework for further consideration, it is important to understand how postmodernism has influenced music education. Current practices in music education have led Reimer (2005) toward a synergistic approach to developing the strategies for transforming music education. Both are examples of how music educators

PAGE 30

24 have dealt with issues rooted in postmodern thinking. Still others have diverse views on the subject. These postmodern views are important because they se ek to determine the rules by which knowledge is obtained, and the nature of knowledge itself. It is impossible to consider any argument for musical materials without understanding the rules of engagement. This is perhaps the most difficult task, simply bec ause the nature of postmodernism is somewhat elusive Nevertheless, postmodern thought is a driving force behind contemporary socio political views in the United States and is a key variable toward finding common ground inclusive and stable enough for laun ching an argument. Furthermore, it at least serve s to explore for the reader one of the root causes of some problems in selecting musical materials in music education.

PAGE 31

25 Chapter 3 Postmodernism, Multiculturalism, and Musical Materials In order to argue what music education is or should be for, it is important to lay out a framework for making arguments. If the framework can not be established, then music educators are forever resigned to taking sides with little impact. Reimer (2005) mak es a valiant and successful effort toward this end in his philosophy of music education by attempting to develop a synergistic approach between various points of view. Jorgensen (2003) develops arguments in Transforming Music Education by summarizing socie with that solution furthering music education (p. 12) Small (1996) works from his perspective of a flawed Weste oriented framework. There are many other perspectives as we ll, but one of the unifying features of all of these philosophical approaches is the need to address music education, at least in part, within a post modern context. Therefore, it is critical to understand to some degree the concepts provided by postmoderni sm before any attempt to justify the use and consequent non use of musical materials in the classroom. The discussion of postmodernism is important in that it provides a philosophical foundation for multiculturalism and issues of social justice that are re levant to current educational practices in the United S tates and around the globe. Multiculturalism and social justice are directly related to the selection of musical materials in the classroom, and provide philosophical bases for the inclusion of certa in materials for many music educators (Elliott, 1995 ). But there is some concern that music

PAGE 32

26 cussion of multiculturalism and social justice in a postmodern framework explore s some of the most fundamental philosophical perspectives of these positions and their impact on music education. Before continuing, however, it is important to characteriz e the brief explanations of these concepts that follow. The literature on postmodernism, multiculturalism, and social justice is vast, diverse, complex, and somewhat volatile, and any hope for a comprehensive or conclusive summary is an illusion Instead, I simply attempt to provide a brief introduction that s h o w s the problems as well as solutions postmodernism create s for the selection of musical materials in the classroom. Postmodernism Perhaps the best place to begin is to understand the context of the word modern analysis of the development of a belief system over time rather than any particularly tangible methodology it may embrace. Knowledge, as understood within the modernist framework, i s primarily objective in nature. Contained within the modernist belief system are the primary perceptions of the objectivity of science and the existence of universal rather than cultural morality. In addition, art was considered apart from its cultural constraints (Harvey, 1989). Modernism also embraces concepts of rational thought and universals (Rosenau, 1992). In essence, modern thought shaped the industrial world as experienced in the United States, and consequently the insti tutions of which it is made, including educational philosophies, curriculums, and methodologies. Postmodernism fundamentally can be seen as a reaction or an alternative to

PAGE 33

27 modernism, even if only by the structure of the word itself. However, attempts to define postmodernism are rejected by some postmodernists (Usher & Edwards, 1994). Elliott (2001), instead, gracefully begins approaching his working definition of postmodernism Postmodernism does not refer to a systematic set of premises and strategies; it is not a cohesive philosophy; it is not a method of inquiry; it is not an identifiable cultural movement. (p. 34) The nature of postmodernism here is somewhat elusive as a n incohesive philo sophical construct with a general tendency to filter all thought through itself. Post modernism, then, can be understood as challenging some of these previously held belief systems of modernism (namely the concept of objective observation) However, thes e belief systems exist inextricably at the same time (McGowan, 1991), producing increasingly complex relationships between historical perception of reality philosophical frameworks of reality, and contemporary practice. Beck (1993) points out that reality is neither completely objective n or completely constructed : W e mold reality in accordance with our needs, interests, prejudices, and cultural traditions . again and again reality surprises us (as modern science has shown) in ways that co mpel us to mod ify our ideas. (p p. 3 4) It soon becomes apparent that each and every consideration in relation to musical materials for use in the classroom is subject ed to the framework s of the modern and postmodern perspectives. Even considering music as a material at all needs consideration and clarification before proceeding further. It becomes appropriate then to look more deeply at how these problems have been addressed by others. Since culture is considered

PAGE 34

28 to be the lens through which all knowledge is filtered (B eck, 1993), the primary goal here is to clarify what culture is, and its role in music education as seen through the eyes of music educators and philosophers in postmodern contexts. It is also important to consider how issues related to multiculturalism an d social justice function as products of modern or postmodern thought. For music education, the impact of postmodernism can be felt primarily through the globalization of educational philosophy, and the consequent education of globalism through the promoti on of ideological frameworks including cultural diversity and human rights. Globalism Globalism addresses, among other things, the many ways in which societies, governments, and individuals intera ct and do business, and is a by product of the end of the Col d War and the spread of democracy (McCarthy, 2004). Globalism, while providing a variety of international solutions, also presents a number of problems. Some problems inherent in globalization include colliding values, economies, and social injustice (McCa rthy, 2004). Individuals and groups become borderless, culture is redefined, and the ideologies of these diverse cultures are viewed within social contexts. As education embraces globalism, loyalty to the community, and consequently, the nation, is comprom ised (Colwell, 2004). Because globalism calls for curricular reform in education, all educators should be aware of this power struggle and its political implications: with every topic having at least two sides, both attractive to its constituency and both meritorious in their own way. In the year 2000, the dominant sides are

PAGE 35

29 designated liberal and conservative. Although these designations need not relate to political parties political connections can be made (Colwell, 2004, p. 18) Globalism has become an increasingly significant influence on education in the United States, offering both problems and solutions for music education. Multiculturalism As a product of globalism, multiculturalism permeates political, entertainment, and education al institutions (Campbell 1993). It is a pervasive ideology that has both positively and negatively perceived political and educational values, which are largely determined by the political perspective of the viewer. Multiculturalism has become a formidable ideological reference for promoting a more diverse music education curriculum. Music, as a global phenomenon, is especially situated to serve this philosophy for educating society in a diverse and open world where broad based, open minded approaches are essential components of the music curriculum (Fung, 1998). The International Society for Music Education (ISME) Policy on Musics of the global curriculum by developing guidelines supporting these ideals. Included within these principles are concepts of multiculturalism: It is well known that music often plays a major role in the integration of culture and the maintenance of ethnic identity as well as in mediation among cultures in contact. Further music has been proved to be of special usefulness in the solution of social and political problems in inter et hnic and multi ethnic societies (Lundquist et al., 1998, p. 18) The United Nations Educational, Scientific and Cultural Organization

PAGE 36

30 (UNESCO), music and its preservation (McCarthy, 2004, p. 24). In 2005, the UNESCO Convention on the Pro tection and Promotion of the Diversity of Cultural Expressions in Paris produced a document outlining its position. Included in this document are a variety of multicultural ideologies, including the celebration of cultural diversity and the promotion of so cial justice (UNESCO, 2005). The philosophical and praxial concepts of multiculturalism have been investigated in numerous areas of research, and there is some disagreement about its meaning (Miralis, 2006). The term culture has evolved in its meaning over the last few hundred rational and nonrational; culture is a totality of values, beliefs, and behaviors common to efore, cultural makeup diversity within a pluralistic culture. The multicultural ist is viewed as being cosmopolitan, having an expanded view incorporating tolerance of the world and its inhabitants (Vaugeois, 2007). This view has been widely accepted and exercised in higher education circles around the world (Krannawitter, 2003). Mul ticulturalism includes concerns of cultural inequality. Banks (2004) outlined the dimensions of multicultural education as school cultur

PAGE 37

31 vary. McLaren (1994) defined these various perspectives as liberal, conservative, or The use of these classifications is important for McLaren and other (McLaren, 1994, p. 53). While n o t all proponents of multiculturalism share this perspective, i t warrants further consideration. Equality is achieved in part by reflecting and representing cultural diversity in the schools. In addition, social reconstructionists desire to promote diversity while teaching students to challenge social inequality. From this perspective, the curriculum includes the promotion of human rights, ranging from respect for diversity of lifestyle to a just distribution of power and income. Similarly, multiethnic education seeks to break the barriers between inferior and dominant groups in part by providing equal opportunities and promoting ethnic diversity. Article 16 of the 2005 UNESCO C onvention in Paris illustrates these ideals: Developed countries shall facilitate cultural exchanges with developing countries by granting, thr ough the appropriate institutional and legal frameworks, preferential treatment to artists and other cultural professionals and practitioners, as well as cultural goods and serv ices from developing countries (p. 9) In music education, limited research has been devoted to the uses of appropriate terminology when addressing diverse musics. A review of the literature on the terms, multicultural, multiethnic, and world music education by Miralis (2006) outlines various titles in music education research that i ncorporate these terms, as well as terms used interchangeably with multicultural such as cross cultural and intercultural, and terms

PAGE 38

32 used interchangeably with multicultural music such as ethnic music, indigenous music, and world music Miralis (2006) point s out that this variety in terminology may be a result of diverse approaches of incorporating multiculturalism in music education. While some educators may view these terms as having identical meanings, each has its own philosophical approach in practice. World music, originally contrived as a tool of differentiation from Western classical music, has come to mean various types of music from around the world. In this light, global music is presumed to be more accurate, differentiating it from the phenomenon of instruments and styles present beyond their culture of origin (Miralis, 2006). Multicultural music education carries with it a philosophy that is more focused on societal equality, whereas music educators are generally more concerned with teaching the music of various ethnic groups (Koza, 1996; Norman, 1994). Philosophical challenges to postmodern arguments Modern Western philosophy is founded, a t least in part, on the premise that humans exist in a reality that they did not create, that this existence has order (laws of nature), and that each may judge what is likely to be true. Challenges to modernism are rooted in these premises, and focus on th eir indemonstrability. From t he postmodern perspective, the argument is that the freedom to judge is not really freedom if it can be shown to have a cause. The pursuit of what causes human behavior (rather that the freedom to judge) then, became the focal point of philosophical inquiry across diverse disciplines, as seen in the writings of Darwin, Fre ud, Marx, and a range of others (Krannawitter, 2003). In other words, humans make cho ices because something (economy, psychology, biology etc.) caused them to make that choice, hence the

PAGE 39

33 freedom to judge for oneself is not demonstrable. Krannawitter (2003) points out that Jean Jaques Rousseau rejected classical thought in the 18th century, and that his writings suggested that language (as a precursor to though t) is an effect of causes that produced it (environmental and cultural). The field of anthropology is born of these ideals, and assumes that reason cannot of itself (as a cultural product) produce universal truths about how humans should live. These are de monstrated through cultural diversity, and since objectivity is varied, the values of one culture are not comparable to another. From this philosophy, multiculturalism has its birth as a non judgmental ideology (Krannawitter, 2003). However, at least for the staunch individualist, the multiculturalist is presented with a series of perceived problems that should be addressed. One of these is that multiculturalism in and of itself is the product of a single culture. For example, cultural practices in homogen eous societies, such as tribal Africa, the Balkans, and North Korea (Krannawitter, 2003, p. 2). Additionally, multiculturalism, as it tends to deny the universal nature of individual humans, overlooks culture as a universal product of individual human nature. And, multiculturalism arrives at the objective truth of its own premise while denying the feasibility of objective truth, and cannot support itself as being truer t han non multculturalism (Krannawitter, 2003). A cademics like Krannawitter (2003) who challenge multiculturalism in principle present a variety of additional arguments. One of these arguments is based on human history and achievement as it relates to the acquisition of knowledge and its applications. From an evolutionary point of view, this knowledge requires objective evaluation. This

PAGE 40

34 ideology proposes that on e idea can be better than another, and therefore, these ideas have measurable value. As humans evolved, technological advances ( e.g., hunting with weapons vs. hunting with hands, planting crops vs. gathering, etc.) improved quality of life for the individu al and ascertained worth of creation, use, and defense of that knowledge, hence the value of knowledge. This Western philosophy of knowledge is founded on reason, individual rights, and science and technology, which result in a better quality of life (Lock e, 2002). Multiculturalism, on the other hand, promotes the celebration of diverse knowledge regardless of its value outside of its own cultural boundary, and ceases to evaluate knowledge altogether (Schwartz, 2002). Another argument sustains that mult iculturalism, although an agent of pluralism, supports separating people into categories to substantiate inclusiveness and entitlement, although by definition it promotes exclusion (Vaugeois, 2007). Bannerji (2000) suggests s an ideology, both in the sense of a body of content, perspective, multicultura lism is a Western ideology that supports inclusiveness without referencing whom is being included (Spelman, 1988). Differentiation between studying other cultures and how we construct those cultures within hierarchical relationships is essential to exposin g the seemingly innocent nature of multiculturalism (Vaugeois, 2007). In the education literature multiculturalism has been seen (although scarcely) as an agent of socio political agendas that threatens to indoctrinate rather than educate students. In Au stralia for example some view multiculturalism as a politically correct infiltration of virtually every subject taught in the schools. As cultural diversity is

PAGE 41

35 celebrated and promoted, the European tradition based Judeo Christian ethics are scrapped, even though they created and stabilized the current political system based on human rights, law, and tolerance (Donnelly, 2005). Volk (1997) outlines some of these philosophical challenges to multiculturalism as well, but gives little thought to those who cri ticize the implications of multiculturalism. For example, consider the following: Other critics have commented on what they see as the lack of intellectual rigor in multicultural education. They also feel that multiculturalism provides as easy solution to minority student underachievement, and in some cases even see it as a proponents say that these critics really fear multiculturalism because it poses a Statements like these reinforce the current air of the assumed correctness of multiculturalism, and tend to treat arguments against multiculturalism as short sighted. On the other hand, this quote does a ccurately portray some of the accusatory language found in various articles both f or and against multiculturalism, which is more oriented to the point at hand. Still, the vast majority of the literature available on multiculturalism does not deal with thes e challenges. Rather, it is assumed that multiculturalism is the appropriate lens with which to view the world. The premise that knowledge is socially constructed seems to be the only universal conclusion that is possible, making it somewhat difficult to c riticize In contrast with multiculturalism individualism places primary emphasis on

PAGE 42

36 individualist, the perspective on human rights comes from a philosophy centered on objecti vity and reason. The Ayn Rand Institute (ARI) promotes the se and other ideals publications. Individualists bel ieve in the principles of capitalism and reject moral relativism, and a dvocate an alternative approach to multiculturalism (A yn Rand Institue 2010). Not surprisingly, both individualists and multiculturalists take strong and somewhat passionate positions in their writings. Extreme positions on either side exist, but mainstream philosophical and political thought favors multiculturalism in Western cultures and perhaps the political implications inherent in the philosophical bases of multiculturalism and individualism ensure the continuation of these arguments. It is important to consider, however, how the individual is perceived by both the individual and the multicultural perspectives. Both consider the individual to be important. Rather, it is the criteria for evaluating either the importance of the individual or wh at is important to the individual that creates this division. Multiculturalists tend to group. From this perspective, the individual is helped (or harmed) by identifying with, relating t o, or experiencing other groups (Banks, 1993). For those who oppose multiculturalism outright, the value of the individual is the core of their philosophy. Pride is valid only through individual achievement, and ethnic pride is unmerited and is based on collectivism, where the individual exists only to enhance the whole. By taking pride in the group, the individual is devalued, and celebrates accomplishments that are not necessarily his/her own. This viewpoint supports

PAGE 43

37 the achievement of t he individual, and respect and admiration for that achievement irrespective of race, ethnicity, and so on (Bernstein, 2002). The other side of this argument proposes that this view is ahistorical, and as a product of modernism, is vilified through its asso ciation with slavery, personal interest, practices of exclusion, violence, and colonization (Vaugeois, 2007). It is interesting to consider that both views are of Western origin, and both propose that the other is not the appropriate lens with which to view the world. Individualists believe that their view alone is correct, while from a cultural perspective, there is no ri ght only diverse perspectives. It is also worth mentioning that negative products of culture ( e.g., violence, slavery) are utilized as a theoretical building block against Western thought, perhaps implying that these injustices are unique to Western philosophy alone. By doing so, these negative associations with Western ideology are used to define it as a corrupt ed system, and they do not allow for the possibility of corruption within a system, and tend to inadvertently soften perspectives of corruption in non dominant societies. Since multiculturalism strives to celebrate cultural differences, it requires the categorizing of cultures. As previously illustrated, cultures can be categorized by ideology, geography, values, ethnicity, and many other human traits and characters. One goal of cultural categorization is to define the differences between groups toward better understanding. A go al of multiculturalism is to celebrate these differences. Celebrating cultural diversity certainly appears to be a good thing as it promotes the caring and understanding of the world around us. Not many would argue that humans are not better off trying to understand, tolerate, and learn from one another. However,

PAGE 44

38 inextricably implicit within these ideals are the questions of what to understand, what t o tolerate, and what to learn. Multiculturalism, if practiced at a superficial level, may or may not be adeq uate for the facilitat ion of these ideals. One argument is that multiculturalism, if celebrating racial diversity, actually promotes racism rather then extinguishing it. Multiculturalism, from this point of view, is divisive, and limits students to viewin g each other in terms of cultural rather than cultural affiliation) intellect, free will, and equality (Berliner & Hull, 2002). According to Hooks (1994): . if race and ethnicity become commodified as resources for pleasure, the culture of specific groups, as well as the bodies of individuals, can be seen as constituting an alternative playground where members of dominating races, genders, sexual practices affir m their power over the intimate relations with the other. (as cited in Razack, 2006, p. 5) The unfortunate result of using racial categorizations as a basis for equality is that these categorizations do not provide equality for either cultures or individu als. Instead, the various criteria for measuring equality are determined by, once again, some dominant cultural perspective. Music Education and Multiculturalism In music education, the promotion of world musics and musical diversity as a general theme has gone largely uncontested. Because musics of the world are so readily available through technology, musics of the world are being shared, fused, and reinvented. Music educators are desirous to enhance student experiences by fostering

PAGE 45

39 awareness and under standing these rich and diverse musics, and music education research stands to benefit from studies incorporating more than one culture (Fung, 2005). Diverse cultures can better understand one another through music, and are seen as tools for expanding musi cal goals to include tolerance and solving shared problems (Elliott, 1995). Music is advocated by Fung (1998) as a tool for open mindedness because of the general positive attitudes expressed toward music around the world. Music, although a universal pheno menon, contains elements that are confined to culture: The foundations of musical structure and aesthetics in each type of music are fundamentally different, that is, non universal. All musics have a unique history and virtually all cultures have unique m usical instruments. These musical nonuniversals constitute the core of mind o pening experience through music (p. 119) One result of these and other ideas is a call for a multicultural music curriculum that promotes tolerance. By helping people better unde rstand and accept persons belonging to diverse cultures, open minded individuals are to become be less biased (Fung, 1998). However, multiculturalism as an ideological application does not necessarily end here. In diverse educational fields in the United S tates, academics opposed to multiculturalism infiltrating the classroom argue that Western culture is devalued when distorting the values of non Western cultures by artificially elevating other cultures and their ideologies. M ulticulturalism for some poses a threat to the stability and freedoms provided by the ideology that makes them possible. Curriculums in diverse subjects are seen as being distorted in order to make the world fit into the new Western ideology of diversity (Journo, 2004).

PAGE 46

40 What eme rges is an ideological pushing against traditional educational practices via the vehicle of multiculturalism These traditional educational practices are perceived to be connected to knowledge based on colonialist European preemin ence [Eurocentrism] This view portrays Eurocentrism as a narrow view of the potential for education (Brand, 2003). However, b oth multiculturalists and Eurocentri sts seek to provide positive opportunities for students on the whole, so the question becomes how each assess es value. When assessing educational value, multicul turalists tend t o i d e n t i f y w i t h cultural group values, while Western idealists tend t o i d e n t i f y w i t h individual (or universal) values. These are issues that are steeped in political philosophies and present a multitude of additional problems for music educators to consider, some of which is addressed in the next chapter. The most obvious dilemma for music educators comes in the choice of musical materials for use in the classroom. Because so many diverse musical materials are available and there is not enough time to incorporate them all, music educators are left to decide what materials to include. Multiculturalism presents a further dilemma, however, in that the question becomes whose musical materials to include. Inevitably, music education has the potential to become somewhat of a political tool for promoting cultural a wareness and equality. It is not possible to include musical materials from some culture or some group if we choose to label and value musical materials in terms of their group association or identity. Social Justice Because multiculturalism had found wid espread support around the world, music

PAGE 47

41 educators incorporated multicultu ralism as a tool for advocacy. By doing so, music education is linked to g lobal issues of social justice. Vaugeois (2007) calls for a critical hip with political philosophy: Critical exploration of our positionality and our philosophical assumptions is vital to this enterprise. Without such critiques we risk getting caught up in discourses of charity giver while maintaining the inferior position of the receiver. Discourses of charity iques that examine the ways legal, economic and social systems and the discourses that support them produce and maintain systemic injustice can help move us beyond the limits of charitable models (163) Vaugeois (2007) presents the argument that music ed ucators need to use caution when assuming that musical projects are neutral when they may serve as a source of political contes understanding difference is a primary cause for social conflict and . that participating assumptions are rooted in changing attitudes regarding inequality, but fail to address how entified without necessarily identifying social and political concerns. The result is that

PAGE 48

42 multiculturalism does not sufficiently explore the effects of diversity (Vaugeois 2007). Razack (2004) explains: What makes the cultural differences approach so inadequate in various pedagogical moments is not so much that it is wrong, for people in reality are diverse and do have culturally specific practices that must be taken into account, but that its emphasis on cultural diversity too often descends, in a multicultural spiral, to a superficial reading of differences that makes power relations invisible and keeps d ominant cultural norms in place (p. 9) To illustrate, Blacking (198 7) warns against superficial representation of diverse folk songs, and expresses the importance of fighting social injustice, not only through social awareness, but through the potential of the individual. This modernist view of the individual rising above societal injustices tends to demonstrate equality as attainable through individual recognition rather than cultural evaluation. Social injustice is likewise denounced, although the criteria for evaluating these injustices are rooted in individual rather t han cultural perspectives of h uman value. For music educators then, using diverse musical materials does not necessarily achieve the goals of the multicultural agenda. Some educators have provided warnings against multiculturalism citing the problematic n ature of cultural hegemony (originating in Marxism) and misunderstandings of culture itself. Rather than focusing on groups, some argue that music education should focus on human diversity and development. For example, o ne point of view argues that music a nd the arts are essentially aesthetically motivated activity grounded in the positive ways while simultaneously yielding insight into human existence and natural

PAGE 49

43 pheno itself for the individual human in that, This view comes into conflict with some of the tenants of multiculturalism, and the author warns that postmodernism can be destructive in its radical form (Smith, 2006). A focus on the intrinsic nature of music is preferred, relying on the aesthetic powe r of music to It takes little imagination to understand the difficulty in supporting such a position, yet most music educators devote much energy to supporting it. But there are more practical problems for music educators. Colwell (2004) emphasizes how philosophies of globalization are weakening our abilities in music education assessment by dividing the assessment community, and argues that this trend could be detrimental to music edu cation by stating: convince a school board to raise the priority of music instruction or reward it with additional resources. Data that indicate that 90% of the students can re ad music or qualify for membership in the Vienna P hilharmonic has a better chance (pp. 21 22) These examples may point toward some of the problems of multiculturalism for music educators. Educators who are concerned primarily with formal ism or Western ae sthetics may not embrace a multicultural agenda as readily as others who believe in Elliot t (1995) suggests that music is inherently multicultural. As such, he states:

PAGE 50

44 . any curriculum that is truly concerned with MUSIC education will fundamentally concerned with inducting students into a variety of Musics. Curriculum evaluation should therefore consider to what extent music educa tion whether mu sic programs are teaching MUSIC (p. 29 1) He continues to describe and critique six types of multicultural music curricula: assimilationist, amalgamationist, open society, insular, modified, and dynamic Similarly, Volk (1997) arrives at the conclusion that music education should le philosophy of multicultural advocates social justice as an agenda for music education with a laundry list of victims of socio political injustices, and the role musical materials and organizations played in justice, promotes a new agenda for music education. He states: theoretically and practically, I believe we first need to re conceive and mobilize music education as a social movement What this requires, on the broadest level, is that we participate actively in social coalitions for educational justice . We need, for example, to empower our students to make music for social justice (p. 84) He continues to support his agenda, however, by criticizing other philosophical positions: To activate music education as and for social change, our profession will need to sur render longstanding theoretical assumptions that, having nothing to do with social justice, block our advance. One such assumption is the aesthetic notion that

PAGE 51

45 music consists of works whose value is intr in the sounds themselves (p. 85) More about th is is discussed later in Chapter 4 F or now it is sufficient to recognize the polarizing potentia l of postmodernism in education. Summary Multiculturalism can be more than a sharing and understanding of di verse cultures. If applied in its more liberal context, it promotes a political agenda of social justice and diversity founded in postmodern philosophy and m usic educators are rightfully concerned with evaluating the role of music education in society, and desire to find better ways to serve students in diverse contexts. The use of precise terminology is important when expressing a philosophical base for incorporating diverse musics into the classroom (Miralis, 2002). However, we can also consider that m usic educators can (and do) function effectively while supporting a wide range of socio political views, some of which are morally opposed to each other. Still, o ne need not embrace extreme postmodern concepts of multiculturalism or individualism in order to find and promote value in diverse musics, nor should one promote materials believed to be inferior or morally reprehensible ( Jorgensen, 2003). Philosophies of political, social, and individual values are diverse, and provide considerably for perspectives on diverse musics. If music educators desire t o assign value to diverse musical materials it i s important to consider the diverse perspectives of valuing musical materials that are similarly pres ent across diverse cultures, and within a culture. This process begins by exploring the perspectives of the individual, the group, and the human universal, and how these operate together.

PAGE 52

46 Chapter 4 Philosophical Perspective of Musical Value Theory of Valuation describe s content and object 1962, p. 209). Furthermore, effort is seen to be contained within desire as we relate to the world around us. We value something because it promises the realization of something, making the idea of valuation fundamentally His first of three conclusions is most relevant to this discussion: There are propositions which are not merely about valuations that have actually occurred (about, i.e., prizings, desires, and interests that have taken place in the past) but which describe and define certain things as good, fit, or proper in a definite existential relation: these propositions, moreover, are generalizations, since they form rules for the proper use of materials (p. 210) One of D s in nothing other and nothing less than the possi (p. 213). He continues the argument for critical inquiry: When this process is examined, it is seen to take place chiefly on the basis of careful observation of differences found between desired and proposed ends (end view ) and attained ends or actual consequences Agreement between what is wanted and anticipated and what is actually obtained confirms the selection of cond itions which operate as means to the desired end; discrepancies, which are experienced as frustrations and defeats, lead to an inquiry to discover

PAGE 53

47 the causes of failure. (p. 214) Dewey also insists that these valued ends are not independent from their mean s Rather, as in the physical sciences, causes and effects are not final, but continual. He continues: If this principle, with the accompanying discrediting of belief in objects that are ends but not means, is employed in dealing with distinctive human phe nomena, it necessarily follows that the distinction between ends and means is temporal and relational. Every condition that has to be brought into existence in order to serve as means is, in that connection, view, while the end actually reached is a means to future ends as well as a test of valuations previously made. Since the end attained is a condition of further existential occurrences, it must be appraised as a potential obstacle and potential resource. ( p. 215) Valuation, according to Dewey takes place when a particular need is present, and in view are It would seem to follow that for music education, materials can b e considered view, or the diverse benefits of a material when it is utilized in diverse ways. Humans simply value things differently having no perceived shared absolute value or standard perspective of need. Hence the need to consider the view as a perceived function of the material becomes important to the discuss ion of the means (the materials). What is the value of music? There are as many answers to this question as there are people. Furthermore, there is a multipli city of answers within each individual or group. Even the question itself contains a wide range of interpretations that need

PAGE 54

48 clarification. What is music ? What is it to value something? When is it to value something? These questions are so broad and deep in nature, they leave little hope for returning to the original question with sure footing. Inevitably for educators the question becomes: what should the value of music be, for whom, and when? However, we can also consider more objective ap proaches to th e same question. For instance, w h at has been the value of music? In what ways is music valued? Here, i t becomes necessary to pursue the nature of value itself, whether it repr esents a hierarchical structure and the boundaries of such a structure T he cont extualization of these questions is important to the postmodernist, while the content attracts the more objective The goal of moving toward answers to these questions is important when considering the value of music education as a whole allowing the valu e of diverse musics to be critiqued more freely among equally diverse individuals and groups as the framework for necessary comparison becomes agreeable as reflected in the goa ls embraced by music educators. Consider first that music is a broad label in a nd of itself and contains materials that may only be connected by a single unifying factor, such as rhythm, or m elody, or even sound. In essence, the actual sounds of performed musical materials can be so different as to warrant further categorization. Ima gine you are sitting in a class when the teacher announces that she is going to play a recording for you. As an individual, you may assume that you will be able to categorize the material as soon as you begin to hear it. It may be familiar, or unfamiliar. It could also share similar characteristics to other familiar musical materials. The class might react similarly, depending on the cultural makeup of the group, but each individual perspective is somewhat unique.

PAGE 55

49 Now consider playing the same recording t o two di stant cultures. Comparative reactions between the two groups are most likely different. However, it could be that all of the individuals in both groups share at least some similar perspectives. If so, these perspectives could be considered to be in herently human in that they are relatively universal due to our relatively similar physiological makeup as human beings. They could also be considered as products of cultural similarities, or even as anomalies. The value of music has been argued from at least three human perspectives; the individual, the cultural, and the universal Reimer (2005) explains: The three dimensions of human reality are, paradoxically, distinct yet compound. At one and the same time, e very human being, in important respects, is like all other human beings, like some other human beings, and like no other human beings. Applying those dimensions to music, we might say that every instance of music is like all other music, like some other mu sic, and like no other music. And for music education the paradox is the same (p. 172) In order to better understand the implications of selecting musical materials, it is then necessary to consider each context of the human condition as they exist in modern and postmodern frameworks. Individual Value are seemingly inextricable from their culture. This is the point that Westerlund (2003) makes when she gently criticizes in aesthetic education. She states: For him [Reimer] learning music is a matter of cognizing inwardly aesthetic

PAGE 56

50 qualities that the musical object embodies so that the social, practical, ethical, or music al concerns become non present or transparent ( p. 47) It is difficult, then, to ascertain the extent to which the individual is a sep arate category from the culture She continues: The perspectives of the social and the individual are mutually constitutiv e but non reductive. Aesthetic experience, too, belongs to the public world and to the world of mind and meanings, to the processes of making sense a s well as to temporal existence . For Dewey, any experience that is mindful, such as aesthetic experience, can never be only inward and private ( p. 48) On the other hand, it would be difficult to argue that a private aesthetic experience is not unique at all If, then, it is unique in some way, I perhaps have some justification for going forward with individual valuations of musical materi als in that, although we may live in the same environment, or interact within the same culture, or even in the same family, the concept of same can not completely describe the diversity of the i ndividual aesthetic experience. We can only have similar experiences, although as Westerlund (2003) points out, this experience is a result of being necessarily shared. F belief as p. 150). What we have then, are musical concepts dependent o n interaction with music itself. E ach mind i ndividually perceives aesthetic musical states described by language. Fiske (1996) continues:

PAGE 57

51 Appearance state. It is where the listener finds a tonal rhythmic interpattern comparison to look like, resemble, feel like, seem like, be like, parallel, approach, approximate, correspond to, or smack of some specific feeling, emotion, affect, desire, passion, sentiment previously experienced or known to that particular listener p. 152) So while it is possible for individuals to derive very similar emotions from musical cultural contract nor inappropriate when it is not share d p. 151) If we wanted to answer the question of what m usical materials to use in the classroom, we c ould begin by considering what individuals value about music, as much of the literature does. Eventually, however, it becomes necessary to delve into what individuals could potenti ally value in music. H ow could which musical materials benefit student s that do not currently have the ability or will to access them? assum e that something is potentially and universally valuable to all individuals, we can at least consider then that the credibilit y of the subjective valuations of the i ndividual are unlikely as well. Not everyone values the same things in music, but there is no reason to if they were willing an m or should not value it in the future. p. 456). In this example, the musical material becomes secondary to a larger, socially constructed valuation system. My point here is not to argue that this individual illegitimately values

PAGE 58

52 his music, but rather that the valuation is incomplete or otherwise subject to influence For example, i f individual recognition of a musical material provides joy, and music has a primary role to play in the joy of recognition, then musical materials could be selected for the class r oom based on their familiarity. T his is demonstrated in band and choral music programs through common performances o f arrangements of popular music expression of frustration rathe listener as someone who consumes Tchaikovsky or Dvorak to confess their unhappiness, p. 462). Ag ain, the point is merely to illustrate yet another reason i ndividuals choose to consume music. However, the problem still exists as to what other values are available to the individual from music, and whether or not the musical material is a primary or secondary source of that value in light of previously describe d social constructs. Kivy (1990) describes the uniqueness of individual interaction with music, writing p. 71). T his approa ch has significant implications for the selection of musical ma terials. If we only treat students as members of groups, we may inappropriately create expectations for students to respond to musica l materials in the same way. Fiske (1996) states p. 153). I nstead, music educators can concentrate on whether or not individual students are given enough information to access valuable cognitive and emotional states available through experiencing diverse musical materials, independent from, but not exclusive of th eir socially prescribed meanings.

PAGE 59

53 In essence, the individual retains the right to pursue personal belief systems based on interaction with materials themselves. Whether or not these belief systems sync with cultural socio political expectations is ultimate ly left up to the individual. Each individual can choose what materials to engage with, and for what reasons they wish to engage. Educators can essentially help students develop tools that give them broader access to the diverse values of musical materials, making the students better equipped to mark their own musical path in the future. Since we have such wide access to materials, e ducators w o u l d have to determine what materials are critical for inclusion in the limited time given in the classroom, for whom they are critical, and to what ends they are essential. A goal of encouraging the continued explorat ion of the ind ividual is to find common ground, or to find the some in universal frameworks among diverse cultures. Beck (1993) states: It is an exaggeration, however, to maintain that because the self is limited, conditioned, and c ontingent in this way it has no signif icance, identity, or capacities. Individuals may be no more important than cultures, but neither are they less so. Individuals are just as unified and characterizable as communities, and they have considerable (though not unlimited) ca edge, regulation. There is no basis for emphasizing the culture or community to the neglect of individuals ( p. 5) If it is the case that the group is no more important than the individual, one implication is that all individuals could theoretically benefit similarly from (or suffer through) all musics, leading to the appropriate question of whether music materials should be selected to reflect the group diversity present in a particular classroom (individuals representing

PAGE 60

54 groups, cultures, etc.), or to reflect the diverse individual values of music for the student universal. The difference is whether the purpose of music education is to advocate for particular groups by social activism toward social justice, or whether music educat ion is to advocate for particular individual human values as reflected by diverse applications of music within and among groups, essentially orienting the value of musical materials around cumulative considerations over p dom inant groups. For example, one could argue that a particular Chinese folksong is valuable to music education because it represents the culture. Another could argue that the folksong is valuable because it contains a unique human aesthetic quality that is not readily accessible in other materials. Still another may conclude that the song is critical for inclusion in order to provide justice for a diverse student population that includes Chinese students. It is interesting to consider that all of these appro aches could lead to the selection of similar materials and similar learning outcomes, even when the criteria for selection are different. Cultural One would think that social arguments would augment the individual argument since society is constructed of the individual as the lowest common denominator. But this is not always the case, and social arguments seem to downplay the perspective of the individual when considering aesthetic value Elliot t (2007) illustrates this friction best: I dare say that thous educators, community musicians, listeners, and students conceive, experience, and embrace music for its social values To these people, music and musical values are not matters of some inherent meaning that resides somehow in patterns of sound, or of perceiving and reacting to

PAGE 61

55 aesthetic qualities ( p. 85) While it has proven difficult to argue universally inherent meaning in sound or patterns of sound (see Cook e, 1959), universally perceived aesthetic qualities become th e target of frustration with current aesthetic philosophy in light of social values. He continues by citing Bowman (2005) who states: which manifests itself most authentically disciplinary concern. Musics tainted by extra or non musical or processual meanings are less valuable or worthy of our attention. Only, as this act of sorting works by a kind of sleight of hand [or ear] that renders i nvisible the supposedly extra or more specifically, by situating their legitimately musical purposes, dispensable. ( p p 3 4) Notice again h ow colorfully the social benefits are pitted again st modernist aesthetic theory. It becomes clear that the argument is deeply rooted in more fundamental concepts of knowledge as described in C hapter 3 From this perspective, Elliot (2007) continues to argu p. 86). But the most important concern is the rationale Elliot t (2007) provides, which interestingly pairs the membership of career musicians in the Nazi party wi th the failure t role of music education for social justice ( p. 87). He

PAGE 62

56 p. 87). Herein lies the individual disposition w ould there is a myriad of social activists whose views of social justice fall into direct conflict. For example, Turner (2009) provides some insight from within feminism: Feminist social theorists engaged in extensive and sometimes acrimonious, not to say vitup erative, discussions with one another focused on the question of who truly represented the viewpoint of women or how to represent the standpoint of particular oppressed groups of women . and t heories were used uncritically except for the central issue o f their utility for the cause. Here, it seems supporting a particular feminist cause in music education could prove to be problematic. For instance, if a high school choir felt the need to this intent in a program in relation to a song, the views of some students and audience members would be necessarily compromised. B y embracing so readily the trends in concepts of social justice paired with the social nature of music, t he moral assumptions of relativism and cultural diversity in the previous social arguments are carefully bypassed momentarily to present the argument For example, a ose the birth right of a child is perceived to be universally moral by some but this posi tion necessitates opposition to those who promote the universal moral position advocating the rights of the unborn Again, whether or not social justice is a goal of music education becomes irrelevant, because the founda tion for such a proposition can not s ustain itself. First, social theory should provide a foundation

PAGE 63

57 being, most scholars seem content to tread on the Eurocentric perspective of knowledge without fear, whi le failing to equally question the morals, belief systems, or behaviors of the underrepresented groups because t hey are oppressed or victimized. From a purely postmodern perspective, this implies their behavior is ju stified as a cultural knowledge Oppress ion and victimization of the group seems to provide a form of absolution if not innocence. The only other reasonable explanation would be a form of elitism, cloaking itself in the seemingly moral purity of multi culturalism. That seems extreme, but if there is no infallible position for advocating on of human rights over another, then these seemingly moral positions being advocated for in music education are highly problematic. But again, the goal is not to question whether this theory is correct or not, but to show how slippery this path may prove to be for music education. By socially reconstructing philosophical arguments for music education, arguments for social activism in music education are embraced more a s a n ideological plight than as phil osophical or theoretical bases, as Elliott (2007) does by his emphatic moral rejection of aesthetics, creating an interestingly moral superiority of the social argument over any other. Indeed, when an argument is presented as being in the interest of human rights and social justice, one who attempts to criticize on the merits of the argument is exposed to being characterized negatively, not in terms of the argument, but because of the argument. When social activism underlies theory and research, it change s the nature of the discussion, and the feasibility of generating sound footing for educational practice.

PAGE 64

58 Turner (2009) describes the lack of common goals between the theorist and the researcher when he writes: . the primary intellectual impetus to soc iological research now comes from the organic relation between sociologists and social movements, which use theoretical ideas, but are driven primarily by particular notions of oppression and injury that are rooted in personal experience and re lated to pol icies and programs. An interesting illustration of the questionable nature of the more extreme social arguments across disciplines was demonstrated by physicist Alan Sokal, who in 1996 published an article in Social Text es: Towards a purposely created a paper riddled with nonsense in order to see if a social journal would actually publish it. Consider the following satirical excerpt: Finally, postmodern science provides powerful refutation of the authoritarianism and elitism inherent in traditional science, as well as an empirical basis for a elucidation of one and the same object may require diverse points of view which this is quite simply a fact about the world, much as the self proclaimed empiricists of modernist science might prefer to deny it ( Sokal, 1996, p. 22) The paper was pub lished and created a lively debate for years to come, but again, Sokal would have us notice the lack of rigor and the politic al ideology that often pair s scholars with social agenda rather than social theory. Still others argue how socio political structur es have impacted music education.

PAGE 65

59 Adorno (2002) criti cized the modern music market pla ce when compared to capital istic music of the 19th century. He state d : The role of music in the social process is exclusively that of a commodity; its value is that determined by the market. Music no longer serves direct needs nor benefits from direct application, but rather adjusts to the pressures of the exchan wherever is determined by use: it subordinat es itself to the process of exchange ( p. 391). From this per spective, Adorno (2002) contended that capitalism ha d p. 391). He continue d : It is now necessary to face the ha rd fact that that assembly of phenomena for which an overhasty and unenlightened musical reformism employs derogatory terms such as individualism, charlanta nism, and technical esotericis is itself a matter of social fact and socially produced. For this reason, the situation cannot be corrected within music, but only within society: through the change of society ( p. 392) provides direct co nnections between social agenda and music value, and again refers to an elusive moral imperative for what music and society should be (in this case, a modernist position as commonly seen in post World War I literature), and the correction of musical consum ption and practice through ideological social reform. Sociological literature related to the arts in general also outlines a cultural rift between what is called high art and, essentially, everything else. This social discrepancy

PAGE 66

60 in valuing art is primarily a function of education, but also is attributed to social status. Pierre Bordieu (1984) heavily criticizes these segregated ways of valuing the arts, and makes light of these hierarchical levels of aesthetic taste. He concludes the article by stating: The denial of lower, coarse, vulgar, venal, servile in a word, natural enjoyment, which constitutes the scared sphere of culture, implies an affirmation of the superiority of those who can be satisfied with the sublimated, refined, disinterested, gratuitous, [and] distinguished pleasures forever closed to the profane. That is why art and cultural consumption are predisposed, consciously and deliberately or not, to fulfill a social function of legitimating social differences ( p. 7) This rationale, similar to that of Adorno, proposes again that the social prism ( the word lens would imply some measure of clarity ) does not account for why perceptions of refinement and the subl ime are dismissed because of elitist associations, rather than considering these as other, equally legitimate ways of experiencing art, open to anyone, from any culture. In other words, my culture is better than your culture is critiqued by my culture b eing better than your culture Some research suggests that patrons of high art are more omnivorous than their counterparts. It is these lovers of art music who may be more apt to embrace diverse musical experiences (Peterson & Kern, 1996). Similarly, Bry son (1997) suggested that univoristic musical preferences based on group identity (race, religion, etc.) are more likely among less educated Americans. If music education is to provide a social appreciation and representation of all groups, the rationale f or group classification and

PAGE 67

61 moral assumptions need to find greater commonality among diverse ideologies. Universal Value The concept of universals is rather slippery from the postmodern perspective. For example, consider the comment by Beck (1993): universal. Once again, however, we should not exaggerate this point, as postmodernists p. 4). Curiously, we have accepted one hard construct of socially constructed knowledge while remaining reticent to part wi th previous constructs, such as reason, which is inconveniently necessary to argue its own demise. Instead, we have adopted reminded of the line in the m otion picture The Princess Bride (Reiner, 1987). On the other hand, on e is hard pressed to argue the existence of universal knowledge or reality, in which case, I even struggle with the terms knowledge and reality being used here, and rather think the terms perspective or constructs are more appropriate. After all, if we uni versally do not know something to be real, it is not universal. Likewise, if I as an individual know something to be real, it can only be real to me, and therefore I only think it and not know it, because I know (universally?) that knowledge is socially co nstructed But knowledge is not entirely constructed cognitively. It is also a biological construct (we all seemingly have two eyes and a nose) and more importantly for music, a n experiential interaction between o ur ideas

PAGE 68

6 2 p. 3). Beck (1993) continues: in Of course, all experience is influenced b even physical things through cultural lenses. But this influence is not all controlling; again and again reality surprises us (as modern science has shown) in ways that compel us to m odify our ideas. We thought the world was flat, for example, but were obliged eventually to change our minds ( p p. But when we consider groups are made up of individuals, and that there is a finite sum of groups, we realize that there is a penultimat e group, or universal group, comprised of the individual, not the society, as the lowest common denominator. And, if we can accept the concept of human as being universal, even though we all are different, then perhaps we can accept other concepts as being universal, such as general musical meaning, even though that meaning is somewhat different for everyone. What is often left out of the equation is the value of similarity. There is no problem grouping apples, even though no two are exactly alike. I strugg le at the reluctance of the literature to consider universal constructs as plausible, even if they are not comprehensive due to limited perspective Therefore, we can at least consider that as long as music is universally constructed among individuals and groups, there remain potential universals in the unique characteristics of music that make it desirable among all. Summary Individual, cultural, and universal perspectives can be useful as a variable toward

PAGE 69

63 determining solutions when the value is not know n yet assumed to be a value, as in past philosophical inquiry (i.e. Kant) of the existence and nature (plausibility) of universal morals. If u niversals are considered to be general, partial, or a s perspectives, not without flaw, but also with curious sim ilarity and having data available for scrutiny, we c an avoid the extreme positions simply because they may not be true I could for example, argue to some extent violent behavior as normative, and kindness as an outlier, preferring the normalized behavior as culturally relevant, and become dismissive of the universal data regarding kindness And, a t some point, it could be important to consider what theoretically should take place over what is the statistical norm, assuming moral constructs as generally un iversal, although specifically different, especially in cultura l applications. It is difficult to defend the plausibility of universals within a postmodern framework M usic is no t really a universal language. I nstead, music is a uni versal human phenomenon that, at best, shares a few common characteristics with language It is also difficult to sustain various cultural arguments in light of the individual. This means that when selecting musical materials for use in the classroom, the choices teachers make ar e not without criticism, regardless of what they choose. Perhaps then we should instead consider partials, individual perspectives, or incomplete frameworks rather than dismissing the whole for a flawed part This is in part the message of Reimer, Jorgense n, and others, and each has a somewhat unique offering to the case for the selection of musical materials for use in the classroom.

PAGE 70

64 Chapter 5 Some Comparisons of Current Stra te gies Various music educators have tack l ed the issues related to the value of music yet none is accepted as authoritative. Still, there are some common threads that run throughout the literature that should be considered when developing a philosophical position for the selection of musical materials for use in the classroom. Materi als are inextricable from their associated meanings in the lives of people, but these meanings are diverse and difficult to grasp. Bennett Reimer, David Elliot, and Estelle Jorgensen, have made significant strides to help music educators develop strategie s to better serve their students. In this chapter, I look briefly at the perspectives of each, and their consequent relation to the selection of musical materials in the classroom within the context of the previous chapters. Bennett Reimer A Philosophy of Music Education by Bennett Reimer (2005) has been one of the most widely read and criticized books in the last four decades in the field of music education. Since the first edition was published in 1970, the text has been revised two times: once in 1989, and again in 2003. With each revision, Reimer has continued to p. understood from the text and related materials. One of the more unique characteristics of this book is the attempted application of

PAGE 71

65 synergism to opposing viewpoints among scholars in order to provide a more workable themselves (2005, p. 30). Synergism is achi eved primarily by avoiding extremes among various positions, allowing diverse theories to explore and promote common ground. To illustrate the concept of synergism, Reimer uses the modernist/postmodernist debate, citing an increasing trend toward resistin g hard line stances in these philosophies (e.g. Haack, 1998; Parsons & Blocker, 1993). These examples highlight the critical importance of balance when considering these two philosophical stances, emphasizing the possibility of common connections between them. However, Reimer also notes that a synergistic approach is difficult in that it goes against the nature of philosophical inquiry toward the singular and the extreme. Instead, synergism requires: . the hard, slogging attempt to discriminate carefu lly among differences and similarities of ideas, to avoid portraying alternative views in simplistic, unshaded ways in order to score points in an assumed argument, to attempt to be as subtle as required for the complexities in question but also as precise as possible so that the proposals can be grasped with clarity and directness (2005, p. 33) However sometimes the synergistic approach has the potential for misrepresenting connections between philosophies where none exist. Reimer suggests that synergi sm differs from other ideological foundations of pluralistic thinking. It differs from eclecticism in that it suggests a sympathetic relationship between philosophical differences. It differs from pluralism in that it seeks to

PAGE 72

66 find commonalities where none are apparent, and it may even differ from the dialectical approach (e.g. Jorgensen, 1997) in that synergism seeks purposeful reconciliation while acknowledging significant differences (Reimer continues to argue for comprehensive education see Reimer, 2 007) The author concludes his introductory remarks concerning synergism by inevitably lead s to an end of the debate (2005, p. 36). Instead, he suggests that the purpose of synergism is to encourage those with diverse opinions to work together rather than separately for the common good of music education. Reimer (2005) points to emerging work in music cognition that offered to strengthen the previous printing. In addition, aesthetic inqui ry presented the author with p. ix). The defensibility of these areas increased significantly since the last printing, and offered much nee music education. By revising the text, Reimer was able to continue to apply the theoretical to the practical. He states: I always relate theoretical ideas to practices of music education. That is, after all, what makes me a music educator, albeit of a somewhat peculiar stripe. It is as natural to me as breathing to view and understand emerging ideas in terms of their use in improving the field of music e ducation (2005, p. x) With the inclusion of new ideas co me s the inevitable modifications to his philosophy as stated in previo us texts, these changes expand and affirm older ideas as well, and

PAGE 73

67 There are several existing philosophical perspective s on music that have emerged over time, and each provides implications for music education. In C hapter 2 of the text, Bennett Reimer outlines the concepts of formalism, praxialism, social agency, music as a unique phenomenon, and utilitarianism as examples of how synergism can be applied to philosophical foundations. In each instance, he suggests that the extremes of these views are problematic, but sustainable to some degree. For example, formalism in its purest sens e (internal qualities of music) (e.g. B ell 1914; Fry, 1924; Hanslick, 1957) is incapable of acknowledging the external qualities of music. Conversely, form is a critical element of music, and the established elements of formalism are undeniable. Reimer states: Form, I would suggest, is denied at great peril. It is overemphasized at equally great peril. Music is too complex, too inclusive, too multifaceted, to be entirely dependent on just one of its dimensions, necessary as each of its dimensions might be. Form . is, I would argue, a necess ary component of music but not a sufficient one (2005, p. 43) also necessitates that the formalist consider other contributors to meanin gful musical experiences (e.g. political opinions, references to particular people or ev ents, etc.) that may account for some meani ng that formalism by itself can not. Reimer makes similar arguments in relation to the other philos ophical approaches (praxialism, social agency, etc.). In each instance, the hard boundaries of each philosophical s tance are viewed as problematic, even though each stance is readily affirmed by the author as having legitimacy.

PAGE 74

68 Once the overlapping areas are found, Reimer argues that these areas can provide music educators with a common foundation for developing the m usical intelligences: The primary mission of every other domain and role a culture chooses to include in education is the same to develop the particular kinds of intelligences each p. 233) doi p. 241). Synergism is the model which can be applied to this end in the curriculum. Furthermore, Reimer explains that the music curriculum must evolve to meet the needs of all students. Reimer states: We cannot simply retain th e performance dominated teacher education programs we have devised, embodying that particular orientation of what music education comprises, and add to it everything else we now recognize must be included. must be achieved ( p. 270) A synergistic approach to music education makes this process more possible than before. Reimer continues: We are called on, by the standards, to do for general music teacher education precisely what they require us to do for the widen its scope to reflect a significant advance in our understanding of what constitutes the knowledge base of music as functionally manifested in its roles . We can ignore, or go into denial about, what they require of us, adapting the m to our

PAGE 75

69 present prejudices by sweeping their demands for comprehensiveness under the rug. I believe we have done this to a large extent, quite naturally under the circumstances of our previously limited vision . ( p. 270). A synergistic philosophy of m usic facilitates a concept of a general music curriculum that better provides for students these many ways of knowing and doing music, resulting in a general music curriculum that enjoys an expanded role in education (Reimer, 2005). A synergistic approach to music education also strives to provide music educators with the tools they need to strengthen the values of music as an educational practice by celebrating the various ways of knowing and doing music. This may mean that all music programs across the U nited States are different, depending on the needs and interests of the co Wha t we need is a music curriculum sufficiently comprehensive to encompass the diverse opportunities music offers people to share its special satisf actions ( p. 241). One of the most important aspects of this synergistic approach necessitates inclusion: the inclusion of new technology (including new instruments), diverse cultures, social interests, and so forth Reimer (2005) explains: Nothing less than inclusiveness, in both our concept of what an effective curriculum is and how our programs can best carry it out, will be sufficient for accomplishing wha the broadest possible opportunities to discover and fulfill their potentials to incorporate fulfilling musical experiences in their lives ( p. 241). Of course, the immediate problem inherent in such an inclusive view is that of time and resources. How can educators find time with such limited presence? Reimer argues that

PAGE 76

70 reconsidering past assumptions for the music curriculum could provide an answer to this question. Traditionally, American music education has focused around the (large) ensemble s a model that, while successful, does not address the musical needs of the majority of students in that so few students are involved in these ensembles (Williams, 2007). A more inclusive strategy might include more non traditional ensembles that students are interested in which can just as effectively (if not more so) teach the various ways of knowing and doing music to students. Or, traditional electives in music history might be modified to focus on popular music history. Additionally, technology can be utilized to educate the musical intelligences as well, from music composition software to electronic and computer generated instruments. These types of programs may better represent student enthusiasm without compromising the goals of music education. Ho sson (2007) stated : If synergism stresses a broad and comprehensive approach, the concept means a relativistic or pluralistic attitude of the music educator towards her/his students. T he music educator must be both open minded regarding the students present musical experiences and to promote new and unknown music. Synergism is something worth striving toward. But a synergistic position makes it problematic for an individual who may be d eeply fond of a certain style or genre ( p. 8) Olsson continue d stressing the differences of the Scandinavian music institutions from schools in the United States:

PAGE 77

71 based on po key issue is how such an approach is connected to the characteristics of synergism ( p. 9) Olsson (2007) discussions of di p. 9). By mixing music philosophical problems that need further examination. Bowman (2003) describes further objections to Reim premise that philosophy should justify music education. Additionally, his synergistic approach is not sufficiently acknowledged by critics. Bowman writes: ew, published here. My inclination as editor is to leave open the question of whether this neglect is warranted or not ( p. 3) However, it is noteworthy that these criticisms are me t with graciousness by Reimer, and p. 5). Perhaps this is the realization of osophy with the world. materials in the classroom, and he admirably points out the inequality suggested in the small amount of students who participate in public school music programs. The question remains as to the time and resources available to implement such an inclusive strategy. This question i s considered further in Chapter 7.

PAGE 78

72 Elliott his former students, David Elliot t who in 1995 published, Music Matters: A New Philosophy of Music Education This praxial approach to music education is in part a rebuttal of the aesthetic approach outlined by Reimer. In his preface, Elliot t (1995) states: I am discontent with conventional thinking; after studying and teaching the traditional philosophy of music education as aesthetic education for many years, I have become more and more convinced of its logica l and practical flaws. Instead, Elliott contextu alizes aesthetics as an inextricable construct of the Romantic period. He explains: In summary, the assumptions underlying the aesthetic concept of music belong to a particular period of Western history and a definite ideology that saw its full flowering i century Europe . The work concept of music not only provided musicians with a theoretical equivalent to the tangible and highly valued objects of painting and sculpture, it served to conceal ve aspects by diverting attention away from musical processes to musical outcomes conceived as autonomous objects. In these ways, music gained a place among the commodity based fine arts ( p p 25) ovided a way to elevate the artistic p. 25). According to E lliott, f ormalists also purveyed the prowess of instrumental music through its formal purity, and composers were believed to

PAGE 79

73 be, p. 25). He continues to define aesthetic perception as: A code of listening that obliged nineteent h century audiences to cooperate with musicians in stripping musical sounds of their social and practical links with the world for the purpose of entering the quasi religious realm of aesthetic experience ( p. 25) From this perspective, aesthetics are cent ered around non existent art objects, and the (to) music ( p. 33). Aesthetic experience is also criticized for its intrinsic construct by explaining that proponents of aesthetics claim no utilitarian value for music, while at the same time ( p. 36). Additionally, Elliot t claims that aest hetic perception and experience divest themselves of all individual, social, and practical concerns ( p. 36). He then Musical sou nd patterns represent the general patterns of an infinite number of indistinguishable natural and artificial processes that are already available in countless objective forms ( p. 37) logical nor comprehensive ( p. 38). For Elliott, there is no place for aesthetics in music education. sic, musicing, and context ( p. 39).

PAGE 80

74 This praxial view of music education is oriented toward musi c i anship at its core. onsideration for the various roles of musical musicianship is dependent Elliott describes a rationale for music by describing musicing music listening values works context and creativity what we should do as music educators, but why we should do it. Again, there is no clear differentiation between what materials should be used in the classroom toward these ends, and what materials should be excluded. Instead, the primary focus seems to be a rationale for inclusion pitted against traditional aesthetic perceptions, making hierarchical judgments not only ext remely vague, but irrelevant. Jorgensen possibility of musi c education from two conflicting positions. The first position assumes these musical materials are best for music education (1997, p. 2). The second position is inclusive of any and all forms of music education according to their diverse cultural 2). In my opinion, there are already two problematic assumptions inherent in these

PAGE 81

75 development the idealistic position represented here necessitates the exclusion of the other. It would seem from this perspective that all biologists would exclude the study of simple life forms in favor of the complex, or that the sociologist would study only the most advanced cultures. In an effort to level the playing field for cultures, it is impossible to develop any criteria for measurement outside of what turns out to be simply anothe r, idealistic not allow for cross cultural comparisons of like materials, essentially forcing the argument that materials div ided by cultural boundaries can not be compa red objectively the very least, this argument suggests the need for extreme caution in evaluating musical quality, especially across musical traditions (p. 43). This accentuates her perspective oriented away from these types of evaluations toward multiculturalism. inclusive ideology of cooperation as fostered by the Gaia hypothesis; emphasizin all things on planet earth comprise part of an interconnected dynamic system in delicate states: A comparative and contextual study of world musics can help students understand cultures other than their own and intuitively and imaginatively grasp the perspec what people have in common and how and foster tolerance of cultural differences with people in other societies, thereby providing a better basis for cooperation (p. 3)

PAGE 82

76 inclusion and exclusion by defining Spheres of Musical Validity The spheres provide spheres include social constructs of the intellect, aesthetics, and musical meaning, and have implications for social networks, music institutions, and political power. As a contrasting argument directed at Western classical music as the epitome of music, she explains these spheres through their development within the family, religion, politics, the music profession, and commerce. By understa nding why these spheres exist and how maintained . music educators can more intelligently and comprehensively All [spheres] do not have equal or universal claim on our attention or support for a host of moral, ethical, political, religious, musical and practical reasons. Some spheres conflict with others. Some are difficult to reconcile with others. Notwithstanding these difficulties, it is incumbent upon music educators to weigh these claims and devise strategies that meet them directly (p. 66) M uch like Reimer, Jorgensen calls for music educators to find ways to work together, even when strong disagreements occur. For Jorgensen, this can be accomplished through a dialectic approach to music education. She describes these pairings as collectively being greater than their individual parts, and includes the following paired concepts: Musical form and context, great and little musical traditions, transmission and transformation, continuity and interaction, making and receiving, understanding and pleas ure, and philosophy and practice. She concludes that no single universal philosophy or method can fit everyone, and that a broader view of music education requires

PAGE 83

77 p. 92). in which people come to know music who follow the directives and suggestions of o p. 93). This perspective still provides some problems for music educators because of the inherent assumptions. First, it is deemed important to assume that all should value other ways of knowing. It is also assumed that these ways of knowing are va luable beyond the realm of curiosity, presumably by applying some type of criteria. In other words, musical materials that are considered valuable by some culture are therefore valuable to all cultures. This proposition is difficult to sustain outside of t he global vision of the world prevalent throughout the Western literature that created it, and requires the perspective of an inclusive belief system to be greater than an exclusive belief system. Thus, simply labeling a musical material by its culture of origin necessitates its inclusion, and by reason, must include it regardless of any other factors becau se it is considered to be music, so long as it is significant to that culture. At the same time, some of the values promoted by those who promote a glob ally example) traditional Western materials. These are moral in nature, and include g Transforming Music Education Jorgensen acknowledges problematic, negative products of society (which would include music) including rejecting (universally) the banal, crude,

PAGE 84

78 perspective, because of its inclusiveness, is greater than other perspectives However, if we are to reject the banal, crude, and violent outside of our own culture, it is unclear how these things are to be measured, assuming that they are accepted within the culture in question. One cultural perspective is inevitably imposed upon the other where no cross cultural criteria are allowed to exist. In order to transform music education, Jorgensen considers music as in terms of what it is for: Music as aesthetic object, music as symbol, music as practical activity, music as experience, and music as agency. These categorizations of music allow more generously for cultural comparisons. For instance, one could compare music as practical activity in all cultures by looking for similarities which can provide data that support similar musical concepts and values across cultural boundaries T he music educator then has a goal for music ed making the inclusion of any particular cult ur e s music less critical to the overriding musical objective s that are shared by so many cultures The diverse ways of knowing from this politic al agenda becomes less critical as criteria for the inclusion or exclusion of materials. Additional Texts There are n umerous other texts that would be appropriate to consider here. For example, the work of Small (1996) is perhaps the most comprehensive philosophical social argument against Western imperialism as seen in its music. The value of Small s writing however, is made even greater by his lifelong p rofessional experience in music

PAGE 85

79 education. His intimate knowledge of and appreciation for the Western classical music establishment he critiques gives added weight to his arguments. His view of music educati the art s Kivy (2002) on the other hand, argues the formalistic values of without nec essarily excluding other values, citing the problems inherent in pairing absolute musics to specific meanings. He also considers Western classical music valuable, in part, because of its formal beauty. He states: What we must avoid concluding is that no music can be beautiful without such features (formal) as I have di scussed, or that having such features will assure its beauty (p p. 86 87) The relevance of these texts is too detailed for the purposes of this inquiry. However, some of t he conclusions of these writers are seen in the analysis that follows. Summary This C hapter provides a context for looking at the problem of musical materials as describe d by three of the most recognized voices in the philosophy of music education. These authors provide us with a general overview of the primary issues related to music education and how they have been or should be considered. As such, the discussion of musical materials for use in the classroom should be weighed against these benchmarks to see how they fit within diverse perspectives. This perspective pr ovid es a holistic view of diverse materials utilized in the classroom, and considers whether or not the characteristics of those materials are availably relevant to diverse ends

PAGE 86

80 Chapter 6 Quality of Musical Materials If there is to be a comprehensive ap proach to the selection of musical materials for use in the classroom, it is dependent on an agreement among the disciplines as to what music is, what music is for, and for whom it is. In each instance, there are diverse answers, and they are not always at odds with each other, or even comparable in some instances. There are multiple materials that may accomplish the same educational goals, and there are multiple goals that may be accomplished through the use of few materials. There are also a variety of uses for music. As discussed earlier (e.g. Fiske, 1996), even a single material of music can not produce the same meaning for any two individuals. These musical meanings may be similar, or quite different, depending on the individual and social perspectiv es from which they are viewed. Individuals and cultures do not always share similar musical materials, and appear to value their own musical materials based on whatever ends they are utilizing those materials for. So, we can compare the ends in view (see D ewey, 1962) to see if they are uniquely served by the chosen materials, or if other materials could provide more adequately toward those ends. In addition, we can consider whether (general) universal ends are being exploited by these materials. To illust rate this point, consider the concept of growth as it applies to interaction with musical materials. Dewe y (1962) mentions ends as being processes rather than actual ends. ( Individuals they categorize present events as happil y ever after). Instead, we put together the means and ends toward new ends.

PAGE 87

81 Thus, as individuals experience desirable materials in real time (ends), they are shaping their desires ( i.e., increasingly acute discriminations) toward other materials, or repetitions of the same materials without The question then, is what has been learned and to what ends? Can thes e ends universally add up to comprehensive music education? Unfortunately, the confounding variables necessarily inserted into these questions make them almost absurd. Primarily, the will of the individual s to determine their own valuations (means and ends ), whether empirically, collectively, or even abstractly or absolutely, creates the problem which is almost solved through multiculturalism, perhaps dependent only on the one stipulation that everyone should ultimately agree on that particular end. For cer tain, multiculturalism allows for reconsidering how musical materials a re categorized and valued. Some musical materials are valued so diversely (or by such diverse perspectives) as to be unified only by their musical definition. On the other hand, materia ls so seemingly diverse in cultural valuations may also share strikingly similar characteristics. It is easier to begin to explore these similarities and differences more accurately by first shedding the traditional labels associated with musical materials and then looking for similar qualities among diverse materials. The available valuations of musical materials are more diverse than they appear in the market place. The sheer volume of music we are exposed to on a daily basis is overwhelming, and the n arrow range of preferred uses of the musical materials is simply too short sighted to revolutionize music education. If only the consumer culture explains

PAGE 88

82 what is important about music, th ere is little room for principles of musical growth and development toward some other end. It is critical however, to understand that musical valuation can be static, and that such an end cannot be rejected as illegitimate. By the same token, such a narrow approach to music cons umption and value is not without consequence. Not everyone wants to grow the same way musically. Some like what they like, and reach a point where they are not willing to go any further. Those who repeatedly order the same item from the menu at a restauran t can empathize, but from an ed ucational perspective, this can not be the end goal for everyone, or else education would become impotent Humans can grow musically in a variety of ways, because humans value music in a variety of ways. Many music educators lean heavily if not exclusively on the social context of musical materials in order to find value. However, as Lucy Green suggests: but that its value is always derived from its social contexts. Whilst I do believe that this must be so, I am not content to follow this through in such a way as to suggest that all music is equally valuable or equally valueless. On the contrary, I believe that both the ways in which the musical mater ials are put together musical evaluations, do form important, relevant and genuine claims for musical value . What the concept of music al ideology cannot and should not do, is allow us to slip into a position of total relativism from which we (2003,

PAGE 89

83 p. 22) A comprehensive approach to achieving musical goals in education t hen depend s on the ability of the materials and the perceptions thereof to find and promote common value for all concerned. This process necessitates critical examination of musical materials from a variety of value perspectives; an elusive and polari zing task that depends on unbiased perceptions, something that Green (2003) suggests is impossible. However, the quality and meaningfulness of musical materials is common among cultures, and is a good place to begin moving toward assign ing musical material s for use in the classroom, regardless of the diverse criteria for such determinations. Composers, performers, and listeners all play a role in determining the quality and meaning of a musical experience. In the following discussion, the broader concept o f refinement is considered as it applies to musical materials. Since musicians typically practice music in order to achieve greater quality of performance (typically understood as musicality, pitch accuracy, technique, etc.), the question of why one musica l idea is rejected over another arises. Additionally, similar musical meanings may be realized from diverse materials, and diverse musical meanings may be derived from a single musical material. By considering quality and meaning in music ed ucation, it becomes possible to consider materials for their similar musical characteristics and how they relate to common valuations among humans around the world. Quality of Materials One of the most appropriate ambitions for any music educati on program that can be helpful when considering the valuation of musical materials for use in the classroom is the concept of quality. This concept can be readily applied to most if not all musical

PAGE 90

84 materials (again, assuming also the material as performance). One way music educators can serve their students, regardless of their own socio political ambitions, is to promote er, 2007, p. 9). Quality, or refinement in practice, allows the teacher to provide for students hierarchical ways of knowing and doing These do not necessitate pitting one style or culture over another. Whatever the material that is being used, then the g oal is to get more out of that material, or to use it more effectively. This allows for multiple materials being selected for diverse outcomes unified by their musical elements. To illustrate, one who would like to teach Western concepts of melodic phrasin g at a private, Christian institution, and also at a public school, can do this with different materials while accomplishing the same musical agenda toward different ideological ends. Furthermore, since the concept of a melodic phrase is not inherently Wes tern, it can be accomplished through diverse cultural musical materials as well. Hence, music educators can focus on the quality of the musical phrase while using otherwise diverse seemingly unrelated materials, making the selection of the material depende nt on how well its melodic phrases are constructed. But this is a simplistic example. How does one determine quality in musical materials given the div erse valuations of the elements of those materials? Even if everyone could agree that the refinement through knowledge and practice of a musical material is a goal, the question of valuing what is being refined remains. Is it worth refining in the first place? To whom is it worth refining? Rather than comparing materials (and their parts, both social a nd fundamentally musical) to one another, perhaps it is best to start with a simpler comparison within one

PAGE 91

85 musical material. For instance, one could compare two different recordings of the same song by the same artist. Finding all of the differences betwee n the two would be a challenge. Comparing the quality of those differences would be another challenge. Yet these tasks are accomplished daily by recording engineers around the world. What differences are they listening for? What makes them choose one take over another? If we consider that both takes may be good, and yet still one may be better, we have allowed ourselves to make a judgment about quality based on a set criteria, both social and sonic. what for most would be unnoticeable? And what might these criteria be? Considering what has been described previously, we understand that any two individuals or cultures may select different criteria for determining quality. So the question relates more to the palate available for making quality decisions related to musical materials. Each musical culture, style, and genre has some unique criteria for determining quality. Within each culture, further individual preferences st ill contain determining quality in a specific musical material where the importance in quality in first finding the objective differences between the two takes. These dif ferences could be described across cultural boundaries as well, since preference, ideology, and socio political are not in play. At this stage, education becomes important because it can help the listener/performer to develop the increasing ability to pay attention to or listen for specific musical elements that may be ignored by a cultural perspective. By doing so, the student is empowered to make more informed decisions about the quality of those materials, simply because he has learned to attend to them. This overtly obvious example

PAGE 92

86 is more important than it seems at first glance. For those who teach ensembles, studios, and classes involving diverse musical materials, the realization that many students are not sufficiently equipped to make simple discrimi nations between sounds is confounding. They have often learned to listen without hearing. Furthermore, the quality of musical materials is dependent on an awareness of and the ability to discriminate between issues of quality. I often ask my students to m ake musical comparisons only to realize that they are not equipped to do so. Any private lesson instructor or ensemble director w o u l d affirm that students need incremental guidance when learning to attend to issues of quality. Traditionally, this has been t he focus of music education. Materials have been selected and even graded toward achieving quality. Methods are deve loped and utilized to maximize and increase the quality of student achievement. But there are different perspectives on quality, even within a culture. Some of these differences can be non combative, such as two artistic interpretations of a particular symphony, or a creative re mix of a still popular rock and roll song. Other differences can be seen as polarizing. For example, in the literatu re, Western classical music is often serious is in quotations, either affirming the inappropriateness of the term, or providing a derogatory perspective of th ns. One begins to wonder whether or not any musical materials should be considered to be serious at all It is the comparison that initiates the consternation, however. Serious music is used to by some in order to establish its diverse functions from popul ar or other musics. Hence, we have now become critical of music materials based on their perceived cultural functions, and all further

PAGE 93

87 discussion on the matter creates problems. And to further complicate the issue, comparing musical objects at all is seen to be controversial. Small (1998) explains his perspective: That misunderstanding (music as object) has, as we shall see, had in turn its e ffect on the experience, that is, of the performance, fo r both an effect that I believe to have been more to impoverish than to enrich it. For performance does not exist in order to present musical works, but rather, musical works exist in order to give performers something to perform (p. 8) rooted in music as something people do: Artistic activity, properly understood, can provide not only a way out of this impasse in musical appreciation, in itself an unimportant matter, but also an approach to the restructuring of education and perhaps of o ur society . art is a model for what work could be were it freely and lovingly undertaken rather than, as it is for most today, forced, monotonous, and boring (p. 5) Once musical materials are removed completely from their identity as sound objects, t he rules of discourse have changed. I nstead of arguing what music is for, I must argue what musiking is for comparison to the music act and work, Small (1998) makes the same consideration I have flat for a few hundred in his community as it compares to a famous virtuoso playing the same concerto in a concert hall: Since we are both playing from the same material, maki ng more or less the same

PAGE 94

88 sounds in the same relationships, there must also be a residue of meanings that are common to both performances. Maybe if we knew completely where the differences and the similarities lay, we should understand completely the nature of musical performance. In any case the first step is taken when we ask the question (p. 1 7) Here, the assumption that the sounds of the material are more or less the same creates a bit of a problem when considering quality. O ne is the quality of the sound object (assuming for a moment that there still may be such a thing), and the second is the quality of the act. Other qualities come later, including the quality of the society, which seems to be the concern of most. But as fo r the sound object and its ability to embody something, we can consider a few ideas regarding sound that are not generally perceived to be musical. We derive meaning from sounds that we as humans do not create, but these meanings are still socially constr u cted (birdsong, thunder, etc.) (s ee Cooke, 1959). However, the hu man response to some sounds can not be entirely explained by social construct. For instance, sound that is too loud has been used recently to drive away pirates off the coast of Africa (Axe, 2 008) This negative physiological response to sound is not accounted for by construct, even though we do construct the sound in part. Music cognition deals with physiological r esponses that have implications for musical quality and value for humans (see Do wling & Harwood, 1986). M easurements of physiological responses are often taken in order to determine what qualities are linked to what values, and make both individual and cultural judgments based on that information. In this way, we can treat music as a sound object subject to evaluation, even though we understand that the evaluation is incomplete, and to some, socially irrelevant.

PAGE 95

89 I f I can use loudness, then, as criteria for determ ining how humans value quality, I have to consider the range of these cr iteria and my rationale for making those judgments. It is easy enough when the loudness is imperceptible or brings me to my knees in pain, but becomes immersed in subjectivity once perceived in relative comfort, as most of the sounds in our natural enviro nments are. Retail stores have studied loudness levels of background music in orde r to promote sales successfully This should be some indicator that even passive listeners make quality judgments about sonic musical elements, even if those judgments are no t conscious. Other issues of quality are determined by formal musical elements. For Western music, these are understood to be melody, harmony, rhythm, form, and texture or s ome variation of these elements Each diverse culture values these differently, as do those within the same culture. But if music education is to be comprehensive, the conversation about musical materials need s to begin here. Then, we can move toward how one culture values a particular musical element, or does not, and the role of refinement in that culture. This allows us to discuss the poor quality of a particular material for use in the classroom as it compares to like constructed materials, or its intended valuations. Once the foundation for the discussion of quality has been e stablished, it is important to separate musical values from the polarizing confines of political perspectives promoting social agendas above individual ones. While it is certain that both can be accomplished together, it is also certain that musical materi als selected in these socio political frameworks contains the very bias it hopes to eschew when developing criteria for the valuation of music, and relegates the study of music into another, and seeming ly more important field. Even if this is the case, lit tle room is given for the

PAGE 96

90 individual to operate independently from the group with which they are associated if they aspire to do so. It would be all too easy in this scenario to continue labeling people based on who they are rather than who they can become given a clean slate for their potential and their ability to breach cultural divisions and stereotypes. This would allow for music to be critiqued more freely within and among groups. Even better, the value of musical materials could be constructed withou t disenfranchising groups or making needless differential comparisons between them. With a focus on uniquely music al values, solutions to problems associated with some musical materials appear of musical value to revisit music not only as a social construct but as a human phenomenon unique to each individual, even when similarities are present within cultures. Rather than focusing on the social differences between cultures as expressed in diverse musics, a focus on the similarities between musical materials among diverse groups might produce more insight into the human condition. To do so is to move away from a focus on groups of people d efined by their geography, ethnicity, gender, sexual orientation, and so on and toward viewing students as individuals whose musical interests are vast and malleable, lacking only the opportunity musical experiences to stretch bey ond or across cultural expectations if individual value is available there. Meaning If music is not an object, and individual agreements between individuals within cultures are responsible for musical meaning (Fiske, 2006), it is worth considering the va riance in cultural descriptions of musical materials as an open door to meanings created

PAGE 97

91 similarly among cultures given global exposure to other musics while still allowing for musical perception to function among cultures in non comparative ways. If stude nts are contin uously exposed to more diverse materials, the meanings derived from these materials m ust surely become less distinctive. single field, there is soon but one kind of cattle Authenticity becomes mor e di fficult to define or appreciate, which may be an inadvertently unavoidable outcome. Perhaps the most important focus in music education should be to equip students to develop their own criteria for valuing musical materials. This is not possible unles s students are allowed to experience music beyond their own culture, and educators are free t o open the entire bag of tools ( assuming the old ones may still work) available that w o u l d allow students to explore the possibility universally similar and distinc tively musical concepts, contexts, and categorizations across diverse cultures and time. It is also not possible unless students are allowed to explore music as it reflects and influences their own humanity and individual perspectives on themselves and the world around them. This includes helping student s to become aware of the relevance of music from the past, and puts current trends into a more complete perspective. This perspective would also allow students to not only place value judgments on musical ma terials, but to refine those judgments with time, and even change their perspective of music. The key is for the student to be given adequate and competent exposure to available materials and music experts of diverse descriptions who can navigate the acute discriminations available in each. Adequate exposure nec essitates consideration for all of the fundamentally perceived qualities valued within diverse musical materials. Competent exposure requires the teacher to help the student attend to and exercise th ese quality discriminations.

PAGE 98

92 The meaning derived from musical materials is constantly changing. One young while another in the same classroom may be enthralled. It is not mu ch of a stretch to imagine that both students are not hearing the same thing, even though they are listening to the same piece of music Any number of factors may influence these responses, as the literature demonstrates. However, an interesting sort of me aningful experience emerges among many who study music intently over a life time. Consider the following statement from Small (1987) : For music is, first and foremost, performance, which is a collaboration between performers and whoever is listening, and m aybe dancing; those human relationships which the performance brings into existence are inescapable, and if we ignore them in our quest for ever more ingenious and elaborate objects, then they will become distorted and sterile, just as they do in the wider society of which th e performance is a model. (p. 366) Here, Small describes the ideal nature of music as it exists for him, and many others, within the authentic music making of the amateur as a rebuttal of the Western notion of the sound object. Now if w these two younger students we would undoubtedly see a new set of variables to consider as we construct the meaning of the musical materials. It becomes apparent that the meanings associated with musical materials are constantly changing over a lifetime, and influenced by not only the attentiveness and experience of the listener, but the will as well. Perhaps this is why it is possible for some who have studied music as intently as Small to arrive at different conclusions about what music is, and what music is for. Since

PAGE 99

93 the sound object does not exist for Small, the quality of musical materials is determined through performance and human relationships. However, the point here is to note that it is impossible for Small and the two young students to experience the same meaning from considered equally. They all are listening for different things. So it becomes the challeng e for the music educator to teach the student not what to listen for, but what is available to listen for, and how to attend to it. This is difficult for those who view music primarily as a vehicle for social justice or as a true model of authentic communi ty because it is necessary to promote music toward those ends. For Small (1987), this means that current practices in Western classical tradition are society of the industri If these ends and others are to be valued, it should ultimately be up to the student which of these values to embrace, and the teacher to make these and other values accessible in order for the student to choose an informed meanin gful path through musical materials. For some musical disciplines, this becomes difficult in that music making and listening require highly developed skill, making them inaccessible without individualized or specialized instruction. As such, general music instruction may not be capable of allowing students to adequately explore specialized musical meanings and experiences. Conversely, limited exposure to diverse musical materials does not give students a proper foundation for making value judgments and broa d contextualized meanings. Summary

PAGE 100

94 It is important to consider why humans individually and globally value music along with why cultures value music in order to better understand what the value of music is. Kivy (2002) states: It is historical musicology and ethno musicology that have made us keenly aware of what has always been so: that music is a deep and abiding force in the human family, no matter when or where t hat family has flourished. ( p. 11) If the process of defining musical values is oriented to ward some framework for the acute analysis and valuation of materials based on the autonomy of the individual perception within and among the realities that govern social interactions between and among groups over time, a more comprehensive set of criteria can be applied to the selection of musical materials for use in the classroom, making the musical label less appropriate than considering the question posed by Jorgensen (2003) and many ple do not share all of these things, as individuals or groups. But in order to build a foundation to support a framework for the selection of musical materials, the previously mentioned problems need to be addressed in greater detail.

PAGE 101

95 Chapter 7 Conclusion So far, I have postulated that choosing materials for use in the classroom is highly problematic in diverse classrooms. Since diverse musical, cultural, and socio political criteria are available for comparison, it is difficult to arrive at a quantifiable sum toward universal or c omprehensive objectives for music education. Given the context of diverse students, teachers, and the various perspectives mentioned so far, what criteria should be used to select musical materials for use in the classroom? To what extent should these per spectives of diverse criteria be agreed upon? Considering the multi plicity of possible valuations toward meaningful ends and/or mean s and diverse valuation perspectives, the question is dependent on a common desire among music educators to develop solution s toward some central goal for music education. This goal is seen by some as critical to the survival of music education. Music Education organizations abound, citing studies toward the value of music education based on a wide variety of criteria. The fol lowing paragraphs s y n t h e s i z e some of the arguments in previous chapters toward solutions for the selection of musical materials for use in the classroom. These solutions are broad considerations toward truly empowering students with the information they need to make informed musical decisions in the future. Ultimately, the student will choose this or that music toward some end of his or her choice. The goal of the music educator is to provide access to increasingly meaningful experiences with mu sical materials as they understood to be perceived within and among cultures. To

PAGE 102

96 begin, the valuation of musical materials is considered as it exists presently in education in the United States. Valuation of Musical Materials in the United States In the Un ited States, music programs in schools are somewhat unique among the other disciplines in that it is simply unclear whether music education is truly an integral part of the curriculum. In 2000, Congress drafted House Resolution 266 expressing their commitm ent to music education, stating that: (1) music education enhances intellectual development and enriches the academic environment for children of all ages; and (2) music educators greatly contribute to the artistic, intellectual, and social development of American children, and play a key role in helping children to succeed in school (A merican Music Conference, 2007 ). This valuation of music education is based on research promoting music education citing enhanced music student performance in other subjects and music instruction is (American Music Conference, 2007). risk students to keeping students (via correlation data) off drugs (American Music Conference, 2007). evelopment and improves cognitive and communicative skills, self (American Music Conference, 2007). Additionally, the Music Educators National Conference put together the following

PAGE 103

97 standards of desired processes and outcomes (m eans and ends) toward a concept of comprehensive music education in the United States in 1994 : 1. Singing, alone and with others, a varied repertoire of music. 2. Performing on instruments, alone and with others, a varied repertoire of music. 3. Improvising melodie s, variations, and accompaniments. 4. Composing and arranging music within specified guidelines. 5. Reading and notating music. 6. Listening to, analyzing, and describing music. 7. Evaluating music and music performance. 8. Understanding relationships between music, the other arts, and disciplines outside the arts. 9. Understanding music in relation to history and culture (Reimer, 2005, p. 250) Here, the only indication given for the selection of musical materials is that they should be varied. The question of why they should be varied is addressed somewhat in standards 8 and 9, but there are no references to the quality of musical materials as there were in previous conventions. Standard 7 calls for the possibility of evaluating musical materials, but the criteria for such evaluation are not implied. Reimer (2005) addresses the general question of whether such quality judgments are comparable among the musics of diverse cultures T he question of quality within a culture is equally problematic : I suggest that there are indeed universal criteria applicable to diverse music but that these criteria must be applied distinctively in each . At the universal level,

PAGE 104

98 the same criteria applied to their work by musicians all over the world are the criteria that can be appl ied to evaluating the results of their work (p. 266) In order to accomplish this, Reimer (2005) first suggests that although craft i s limited to a particular musical style, genre, and culture the concept of craft is understood to be more or less universa l. Second, he adds that the affective response of the music al material can be comparative, again, accor ding to its own cultural design The third considering that 267). Reimer (2005) continues: We must help our students understand that judging music is not a matter just of deciding what on e likes but also of developing criteria that are a respectful of the complexities of music as music deserves. We must also be more helpful than to settle for the pluralist clich that every different kind of music has its own criteria. Every different music is also music, I would argue, and therefore exists at universal, contextual, and individual levels . Identifying some practicable dimensions at the universal level, recognizing that they are played out differently in different contexts, and that indiv idual instances of music can be reasonably judged in light of those two dimensions, allows us to teach what is actually learnable and manageable, and as well, I suggest, phil osophically defensible. (p. 267) Reimer (2005) has opened the door here to the pos sibility of cross cultural judgments of musical materials in the midst of pluralistic cultural values and belief systems. From the psychological perspective of musical meaning, Elizabeth Tolbert (2001) has suggested

PAGE 105

99 the value of cross cultural consideratio ns as well: If the social, embodied conditions of representation are to be taken seriously, then cross & 1998) might shed further light on the processes by which musical meaning is intersubjectively constructed in specific contexts. Cross cultural work on how music represents animacy, or a systematic interrogation of the metaphors in music discourse that reference intention and movement, could help elucidate ideas about how social essence is tied to musical structures . And finally, and evolutionary approach that understands music in the broadest sense as referring to and enacting the creation o f cultural truth s . (p. 92) If music is constructed to represent or enact cultural truths, it is worth evaluating how well these goals are accomplished within cultures. I f we consider the history of Western musical development, we can observe and trace the development of musical thought over time, giving another context for comparison of materials that is similar to the cultural one. But this is not to pretend that one is universally better than the other. Instead, we realize that one is different than another, and nee d only to consider how this is so, not just culturally, but collectively in the universal sense. Many might object to such a consideration because it implies hierarchical relationships between musical materials, and thus cultures. But this conclusion is no t necessary. If we say that one material is more complex than another, then we must also say in what ways such is the case. Then we decide whether or not complexity has value, and for whom it can be valuable. If we say that one musical material is better t han another, we need to explain in what way, and

PAGE 106

100 consider whether or not this way has potential for universal valuation. Any concept of better has to be measured somehow. If two boats race on the water, we measure which boat is better by which one is faste r, even though the slower boat may have a smoother ride, or more comfortable seating. Again, we measure according to what the material is for In the case of music education, we measure musical materials according to not only what they are for, but what w e think they should be for. Teachers of m usic are not dispassionate about the selection of musical materials, and a large part of what they desire is to facilitate the passing of these value systems to their students. They wish for students to enjoy the fe elings they have enjoyed, and hope to help them navigate through the sonic world in search of meaningful but elusive organizations of sound in time. Teachers of music have become experts in discriminating between sounds and organizations of sound, and have developed meaningful relationships with musical materials based on why they value them. The differences in the vision for music education in the United States between music educators has little to do with what music is and everything to do with what musi c is for. Music education, then, becomes what it is today an agent for something non musical. Thus we discuss music (as object or action) education in terms of meaning, form, culture, or some other perspective or agenda. Valuations as Conflicting Ideolo gies Much effort in research is devoted to establishing and validating differences. For example, biologists isolate living organisms into hierarchical categorizations. These categorizations include physical realities that are observable, and more readily p alatable as truth or reality (i.e., lions eat zebras). Additionally, there are generally few moral

PAGE 107

101 assumptions to cloud our observations (i.e., lions should or should not eat zebras). One run s into more difficulty when considering human observations (human s are sexually active) because of the diverse moral implications contained within biological information (adult humans should not be sexually active with children, even if they desire to do so), and individuals arrive at different conclusions as to what is just or equitable and what what should or should not be moral, but such norms are not disconnected from diverse since it is the case most communities agree that we should not commit murder, we have decided that it is Instead, morals are perceived by many as having diverse origins (mythology, religion, philosophy, etc.) that can t hen be applied to social When individuals collectively and appropriately perceive of diverse actions and their consequences for others, we make determinations toward values based on perceptions of equality and justice, which are ideologically constructed more so than observationally determined. As described in the previous chapters, the se valuations can be individual, collective, or even generally universal perceptions. Music education research is filled with these moral implications, as seen in a recent article by Louis Bergonzi (2009) appearing in Music Educators Journal entitled, Sexu al Orientation and Music Education: Continuing a Tradition As a professor of

PAGE 108

102 to examin e how homophobia and heterocentricism bias our curricular content and the lives and work of LGBT (lesbian, gay, bisexual, or transgender) music teachers (p. 25). and LGBT individuals in part through better understanding and teaching musical materials and their associations with the sexual lifestyles of composers and performers associated with them. For example, Bergonzi (2009) suggest s that this can be done by context as his sexual relationships with women). There is little 2009) intent is positive, and that his thoughts are supported adequately by research in various disciplines. He is obviously desirous, as most are, to meet the needs of students and to prevent any harm that might result from the materials and perspectives being introduced. The goal of consideration for all is a positive one, and Bergonzi (2009) perceives reinforcing the GBLT community in values are not shared by all, and t herefore the argument is problematic. If, however, we propose to incorporate the relevant LGBT community information in the classroom, yet without promoting or seeking to legitimize the LGBT community appropriately as purposed in the article, we have not a T here are other problems in music education that make the problem even more colorful. The Supreme Court has stated that schools may teach all about religion, but without sponsoring religion (Phillips, 2004). This may not be terribly difficult in most disciplines, but it becomes more difficult in music education, especially in relation to

PAGE 109

103 choral music. For many, the very purpose of sung text is not for knowledge of, but reaffirmation of specific belief systems. In t he public school classroom, sacred music is allowed s o long as it does not advocate for religious belief (Phillips, 2004). In this instance, we have a problem similar to the previous one regarding sexual preference. However, while differences in sexual pre ference are advocated for, diverse religious perspectives are protected through a purposive lack of advocacy. In essence, students their belief system or not. The idea is to neither promote nor inhibit religious views (Phillips, 2004). If religious views are to be tolerated, and homosexuality is to be advocated for, it is not clear how one arrives at the criteria for making such judgments when some students in the c lassroom may be offended by both propositions equally. It seems more appropriate, then, to advocate for and promote the characteristics of musical materials in the classroom tha t find similarly meaningful ends and means among diverse cultures irrespective of their specific applications to ideology. Rather than advocating for a specific perspective of a musical material, one can sum all of the perspectives observe d and look for what diverse groups similarly value. It is also appropriate to consider the selection of musical materials for students in regions that are not as culturally diverse, or are culturally unified by a particular belief system. Additionally, musical materials may be selected out of a parti cular philosophical framework, making available to students a particular discipline of music that may be unavailable anywhere else or accessible only with great difficulty, creating marketable advantage. Turner (1989) describes this type of advantage withi n the context of decision: In competitive situations, comparative advantage that is, the advantage I have

PAGE 110

104 over you (resulting from my different resources, skills, information, and so on) in performing particular tasks or beco mes a major element in determining my choices because what is promising for me, as compared with you, will differ (p. 181) Within music education, the value of some programs resides in their uniqueness, and what some would describe as inaccessibility due to social inequality. Some address this problem through making musical experiences such as the symphonic orchestra more accessible to minoriti economic classes. Others instea d reject that premise citing the irrelevance of su ch outdated and imperialistic perceptions of music. And then there are those who seek common ground between these perceptions. These idealistic positions are far less problematic when proposed as considerations rather than hard and fast realities. This poi nt is brought out again and perceive music, students can be instructed in the variety of ways music is perceived in social and cultural contexts. Again, it is notable her e that quality considerations provide a significant alternative to ideological agenda in diverse classrooms. By addressing quality 9). Here, students can consider how well a particular musical material does what it is supposed to do. When considering musical materials for performance, the solution does not work as well. There is a significant difference between listening to or descri bing a song and singing it when the text promotes an ideological point of view not shared by the student. If the point of view is not a moral dilemma for the student, there is less of a problem.

PAGE 111

105 However, considering the previous moral perspective on murder many students would object to singing a song promoting or condoning such abhorrent behavior. But such scenarios happen all the time, especially in opera or musical theatre. For example, the musical Sweeny Todd contains numerous lyric passages that advoca te murder. However, in the context of a drama, or even a concert, such materials are performed willingly by students, and enjoyed by audiences. Many perform religious content by contextualizing the materials in a similar fashion. It is understood that per formers do not always mean what they say outside of the context of singing it. This is important because it provides a solution for diverse populations to perform musical materials that lie outside of their own belief systems, but are allowed in contexts o f suspended belief. Performances that capture the majestic nature of a bygone era, or perhaps the plight of the horrifically oppressed are good examples of how students can engage meaningfully with musical materials they would not promote outside of their intended context. Still other materials are valued primarily because the materials are contextualized as being authentic and meaningful in real, everyday life. Christopher Small advocates such musical experiences of African Americans in Music of the Common Tongue (1987), where the music is an honest representation of the beliefs and social realities of the individual or culture. Materials like these, properly contextualized, depend on sincere belief in the message presented in the lyrics. Both performer and audience commune with one another through shared ideology. But musical materials may be perceived from both perspectives simultaneously by diverse students. A traditional Christmas concert offered by many schools across the

PAGE 112

106 United States provides a good e xample. In the current environment, such concerts h ave become highly problematic in some regions. Understandably, students who are not Christians might object to performing in these concerts. Other students who are not Christians may contextualize the perf ormance as being disconnected to real life, and have no trouble performing at all. And, still others may find value and meaning in the reality of the lyrics as they perceive them in real, everyday life. Music educators, then, can find solutions by underst anding the nature of their students and the belief systems that exist within a community. Additionally, music educators should consider their own belief systems, and how applicable they are in the community. It may be that in one community, the educator wo uld need to find acceptable alternatives for a few students who may choose not to participate in certain concerts. In another, the same concert should be scrapped entirely for something that is more inclusive. The real problems occur when solutions are pre sented as overriding, one size fits all propositions to applied equally everywhere. Such broad policies lead are too restrictive for all concerned, and are disingenuous toward communities generally support musical activities not desired in other communitie s, whether ideologically or otherwise. Rather, multiple solutions are available. Decision Perhaps one way to address the problems inherent in the selection of musical materials is to look at the natu re of problem solving There is quite a difference between choosing a song for a local concert and choosing a set of valuations for a music curriculum across the United States. This difference is seen in how we approach a

PAGE 113

107 p. 178). For music educators, the structure of the problems being addressed in this paper includes not only the cognitive science of music, but the conflicting social views previously outlined. Herbert Simon (1977) provi des two categorizations of problems in terms of how they are structured. Well structured problems occur within definable parameters and solutions are found within specified areas. Ill structured problems include the complexities of time, multiple definitio ns or perspectives, and may have multiple solutions. Turner (1989) used these concepts to illustrate problems in scientific belief, stating: It would be convenient if the contrast between scientific belief and decision co uld if decision always meant ill structured problems, and science had only well structured problems. Alas, this is not so (p. 178) He continues by illustrating decisions that scientists make based on assumptions, belief, and specific knowledge toward a variety of possible solutions: But a particular kind of resolution, one that makes the facts everywhere the same, or reduces phenomena to a single general frame of reference, is a conscious goal in science, although it is always pursued with the recognition that i t may be that the fact can be further reduced, that our information is incomplete, and that our best founded beliefs about the basics may prove wrong (p. 180) But solutions (beliefs) are not the same as decisions: In contrast, decisions are forced choices where not to decide is usually to that is, to produce consequences that might have been avoided . they require a frame or definition of the situation that is more or less fixed, usually by

PAGE 114

108 taken for granted factual beliefs, by assumptions abou t the costs of improving these beliefs, by the personal limitations of the decision makers, and by the limitations on their powers and other practical limitations (p. 180) Using this contrast between belief and decision helps illuminate the differences b etween well structured and ill structured problems. He continues: . ill structured decision problems, most notably those involving alternative descriptions of the situation some of which are congenial to certain strongly held beliefs or interests of pa rticular groups of persons relevant to the decision, or reflect familiarity or experiences with different aspects of parts of the problem proceed differently from decisions on well structured problems, where the range uncontroversial (p. 180) For the purpose of this inquiry consider ations for the s election of musical materials are a problem. As previously seen music educators often disagree and have strong beliefs and one can also include socio political interests, cul ture, and even taste or preference. Then, adding in the initial intention of bringing th ese considerations to a classroom full of culturally diverse students, the decision becomes highly complex, and the solutions are multiple, and consequential. For Reim er (2005) the solution to the highly complex problem of music education is found in his model of synergism. Jorgensen (1997) chooses a model that considers this

PAGE 115

109 with that Both examples can be observed from the decision perspective in the preceding paragra phs, and provide solutions that are malleable rather than rigid, allowing for time and circumstance to weigh in on the problem as diverse hypothesis flare up in the literature, some leaving their mark notably on the decision, such as multiculturalism. Stil l, the solutions given by various music educators also have their differences, and prefer not to embrace such fluid solutions. At the same time, each position assumes to have the more contextual perspective. Western classical music, for instance, finds its elf in a relatively stable position in higher education in the United States. Most colleges and universities have traditional ensembles, and colleges of music within these institutions primarily study music through traditional Western instruments and ensem bles. While change is occurring, it is a slow process. In the mean time, scholars continue to chisel away at this idealistic monster created by the Western society. Others continue to build it up through musicology, Western theory and composition, and the continued in depth study of Western music history. For these individuals, Western music is contextualized through its development, its artistic value, and its preservation and continued progression. For others, such a perspective is considered to be impro per. Jorgensen (1997) states: At least two contrasting stances might be adopted in seeking to understand music education. First, assuming that Western classical music represents the epitome of musical development and Western music education is the ideal or quintessential form of music education, only Western music and music education are worthy of study. Other forms of musical education, especially those in preliterate or preindustrial societies, cannot safely be relied upon to provide a sound basis for

PAGE 116

110 mus ical instruction. Second, our study broadens to include all forms of music education, irrespective of their societal derivation. When world musics are assumed to be understood contextually and comparatively according to many different value systems, Wester n classical music is seen as only one of many diverse musics rather than the ideal, each music is properly studied within the context of its own tradition in ways consistent with that particular musical tradition, and Western musical education is only one of many ways by which people come to know music (p. 2) Notice how quickly the idealistic label is attached to Western classical music (and in a way rightly so, as many of its proponents promote its legitimacy with unsustainable arguments), and the word pr oper is attached to world musics. The assumptions here are problematic, firstly in that proponents of Western classical music have equal claim to proper contextualization, and a variety of ways to support such claims. The second is that the proper perspect ive is not idealistic, but dispassionate. Jorgensen (1997) explains her point of view: The latter view offers a contextual rather than an idealistic view of music making and music education, a basis for a broad and dispassionate view of music education, on e that seeks to be faithful to all the classical, folk, and popular musical traditions of the world (in comparison to the more limited and culturally biased conception of music education implied in the former view) (p. 2) If a view of Western music is lim ited, it should be stated in what ways these limitations exist, and toward what ends. This is why the social perspectives of the previous chapters are so important to

PAGE 117

111 understanding why music educators are making diverse arguments. For Jorgensen (1997), on e end is cooperation and tolerance. She states: A comparative and contextual study of world music can help students understand cultures other than their own and intuitively and imaginatively grasp the perspec what people hav e in common and how and foster tolerance of cultural differences with people in other societies, thereby providing a better basis for cooperation (p. 3) Music education becomes a tool for fostering idealistic ends. My argument here is not that such a position is wrong, but that this position does not depend on the legitimacy of the other. The argument presents itself by unnecessarily and indemonstrably confining the value of Western classical music. It could be the case that the study of Western classical musics can provide a sound basis for music education alone, without consideration for folk and popular musics if the ends are valued by the culture(s) in question. It could also be that folk and popular musics alone could provide a sound basis f or music education. The end argument is essentially that all cultures should study all musics in order to achieve some ideological end. Whether or not all cultures agree on that particular end seems to be irrelevant, not only to the Western classical ideal ists, but the progressive idealists as well. There are so many considerations, the problem is ill structured, and the solutions are essentially compromises, and do not consider the status quo in music education as the best solution. One method of problem solving that emerges from such complex considerations is satisficing Satisficing seeks for a solution that may not always be the best one, but rather the solution that is at hand for the moment. Simply stated, the solution agreed upon

PAGE 118

112 is a solution rather than the solution. The macro decisions music educators make are well situated within this concept, whereas teachers in the classroom have significantly fewer interests to contend with, and are able to make decisions quickly. Additionally, individual teach ers generally have more practical musical goals for their students, reflecting the realization that we all were, at some point, students who were motivated to teach in part through the materials we valued It is interesting to consider why our experiences with these materials, regardless of their origins, were so deeply valued by each of us that we chose to pursue music further. Solutions The problem for music education is a large one, and infinitely complex. Yet, every day, teachers select materials for use in the classroom with little consternation. Atheists sing religious texts, women play music written predominately by men, young children play the music of Bach, older educators expand their perspective to include popular cultural music, and young stude nts use technology to create musical materials. In the midst of the arguments, music education continues to be highly important to many different people for what must be as many different reasons. The arguments about the meaning of music and its value for humans are inextricable from the ideologies and belief systems we bring to the table. According to the National Center for Education Statistics there are 50 million children enrolled in public schools. About 9 million (this number is steadily increasing) c hildren are enrolled in private schools, chart er schools, or are homeschooled ( IES, 2009). This means that approximately 18% of primary and secondary children in the United States are pursuing their education with a preference for specialization of some ki nd, whether religious, technological, scientific, musical, or

PAGE 119

113 toward some advantage in the marketplace or toward higher education. More importantly, these institutions need teachers and in some cases parents who desire to create their own curriculum, or de sire to emphasize materials that promote their specific belief systems. There is a need for students to obtain the skills they will need in the marketplace that are exercisable within diverse belief systems, and consequently a need for teachers who special ize in these areas, especially those areas that require excessive time and dedication to a singular musical task, such as the mastery of some instruments or vocal techniques requiring years of intense study with highly skilled instructors. Music educators can enhance their selection of musical materials by considering all of the factors that should be considered in making such decisions. Primarily, the music educator should have a firm grasp of how music is valued by diverse cultures while develop ing a deeper understanding of their own valuations of music. And I think it is important for teachers to work out these musical material decisions within their own areas of specialization, especially in current practices in Western classical music, where t view such training as a waste if not fully realized in adulthood, either through professionalism or lifelong participation, I am not certain that this is the case. It may b e that the process of becoming a specialized musician enriches the life of the individual so much so that the process of becoming can be perceived as the end rather than the means. When selecting musical materials, musical quality is important. Materials that are selected for ideological or social purposes should be considered musically valuable among like materials. Also, quality should be considered as having some cross cultural criteria. It is not necessary to assume that world musics are completely inc omparable. On

PAGE 120

114 the contrary, when considering music as a human phenomenon, it seems likely that music around the globe sho uld be and is quite similar from a number of perspectives. Also, musical considerations should supersede all others, including teacher world views. Social justice cannot provide the backbone of music education, and educators that promote ideologies can be confrontational and counter productive to the inclusiveness they strive to support. There is enough to do teaching the music itself. Perhaps music education can focus on giving students a foundation for branching into diverse skill sets. If we seek equality among diverse students by providing equal access to musical materials of quality, regardless of their origins, then we are not doing a disservice. True empowerment is giving all students equal access to information, skill acquisition, and our own judgments about how these can be best utilized towa rd whatever ends they may desire. A firmer grasp of the philosophical consternation regarding musical materials in the classroom may help individual music educators realize the inadequacy of their own arguments, and help them develop stronger arguments in the future. At the same time, music educators depend on deeply held convictions about musical materials as the root of their passion for music education. These not need be dismissed, even when conflicts arise. While diverse perspectives may in fact provide breadth, they do not always provide the intimacy that draws people to music within a many different people. Comprehensiveness is still an elusive task, and while socia l equality is an answer, it cannot be the answer. Rather, music education can provide a wide variety of benefits in as many ways.

PAGE 121

115 Music education as it exists today in the United States is still fairly traditional in practice, b ut the diversity of materi als available, even for limited traditional ensembles, is quite large. It may be that one of the reasons that the Western classical tradition has maintained such a strong position in education is simply because it provides a source of musical valuation and meaning that continues to influence young students. It is not necessary to avoid such materials in pursuit of more relevant musical experiences. On the contrary, these materials continue to provide a rich source of meaning ful study for American students a nd students around the world. Allowing the student access to these and other materials is a good strategy for teachers. If all of the benefits of musical materials were apparent on first hearing, or on the first performance attempt, there would be no need for music education. Instead, musical materials are problems that need to be solved. They need to be listened to with acute consideration for what is being heard, and in what context. They need to be performed within the guidelines established by a particu lar craft, and they need to be valued by students beyond their current abilities. If the materials are chosen carefully, they can provide a renewable resource for learning and meaningful engagement.

PAGE 122

116 References Adorno, T. W. (2002). Essays on mus ic (R. Leppert, Ed.) (S. H. Gillespie, Trans.). Berkeley, Los Angeles, London: University of California Press. A merican Music Conference (2007). American Music Conference. Music Making, Public Policy. Retr ie ved from http://www.amc music.com/musicmaking/policy/res266.htm Axe, D. (2008). Popular Mechanics. Retrieved March 3, 2010 from http://www.popularmechanics.com/technology/military/4285201?page=4 Ayn Rand Institute (2010) Overview. Retrieved Feb 14, 2010 from http://www.anyrand.org/site/PageServer?pagename=about_ari Banks, J. A. (1993). The canon debate, knowledge construction, and multicultural education. Education Researcher, 22, 4 14. Banks, J. A. (2004). Multicultural education: historical development, dimensions, and practice. In J. A. Banks & C A M B a n k s ( Ed s ) Handbook of research on multi cultural education ( p p 3 2 9 ) Bannerji, H. (2000). The dark side of the nation: Essays on multiculturalism, nat ionalism and gender. Toronto: Canadian Scholar's Press Inc. Beck, C. (1993). Postmodernism, pedagogy, and philosophy of education. Philosophy of Education. Retrieved March 26, 2009, from http://www.ed.uiuc.edu/EPS/PES Yearbook/93_docs/BECK.HTM. Bell, C. (1 914). Art. New York: Putnam's.

PAGE 123

11 7 Bergonzi, L. (2009). Sexual orientation and music Education: continuing a trad ition. Music Educators Journal Berliner, M. S., & Hull, G. (1999). Diversity and multiculturalism: The new racism. Capitalism Magazine. Retrieved April 1st, 2008, from http://www.capmag.com/article.asp?id=3425. Bernstein, A. (2002). Pride vs. prejudice: "black bride," "Hispanic pride," "native American pride" are all illegitimate concepts which destroy genuine pride in an individ ual. Impact (supplimental). Retrieved April 1st, 2008, from http://aynrand.org/site/DocSeerver/newsletter_multiculturalism.pdf?dociID=162. Blacking, J. (1987). A common sense view of all music: Reflections on percy grainger's contribution to ethnomusicology and music education. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press. Bourdieu, P. (1984). Distinction: A social critique of the judgement of taste. London: Routledge. Bowman, W. (2003). Symposium: Bennett Reimer's philosoph y of music education. Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education, 2 (1), 1 5. Retrieved September 11, 2008, from http://act.maydaygroup.org/articles/Bowman2_1.pdf. Brand, M. (2003). Dragons in the music classroom: Political and philosophical subtexts in Chinese school music textbooks. Bulletin of the Council for Research in Music Education, 158, 72 80. Bryson, B. (1997). What about univores? musical dislikes and group based identity construction among americans with low levels of education. Poetics, 25, 141 156.

PAGE 124

118 Campbell, P. S. (1993). Music instruction: Marked and molded by multiculturalism. American Music Teacher, 42 (6), 14 17, 67 69. Colwell, R. (2004). Peek at an international perspective on assessment. In P. Shand (Ed.), Music education entering the 21st century: History of the ISME music in schools and teacher education commission and papers and workshop descriptions from the MISTEC 2000 and 2002 seminars (pp. 17 32). University of Western Australia: Uniprint. Cooke, D. (1959). The language of music Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Csikszentmihalyi, M. (1996). Creativity. New York: HarperCollins Publishers, Inc. Dewey, J. (1962). Theory of valuation. In H. W. Burns & C. J. Brauner (Eds.), Philosophy of education (pp. 208 218). New York: The Rona ld Press Company. Donnelly, K. (2005). The culture wars in the schools. Quadrant, No. 415, 49 (4), 56 61. Dowling, W. J. and Harwood, D. L. (1986). Music Cognition San Diego, Academic Press. Elliott, D. J. (2001). Modernity, postmodernity and music educati on philosophy. Research Studies in Music Education, 17, 32 41. Elliott, D. J. (2007). "Socializing" music education. Action, Criticism, and Theory for Music Education, 6 (4), 60 89. Retrieved September 15, 2009, from http://act.maydaygr oup.org/articles/Elli ott6_4.pdf Elliott, D. J. (1995). Music matters: A new philosophy of music education. New York: Oxford University Press. Fiske, H. E. (1996). Selected theories of music perception. New York: The Edwin Mellen Press.

PAGE 125

119 Fry, R. (1924). The artist and psycho ana lysis. In Hogarth essays. London: Hogarth Press. Fung, C. V. (1998). Mind opening through music: An internationalized music curriculum. In J. A. Mestennhauser & B. J. Ellingboe (Eds.), Reforming the higher education curriculum: Internationalizing the campu s (pp. 118 124). Phoenix, AZ: Ornys Press. Fung, C. V. (2005). What can we gain from international music education research? Florida Music Director, 59 (2), 38 39. Gardiner, M. F. (2003). The human ecology of music Retrieved April 15, 2007, from http://www .yale.edu/21c/documents/2007Gar dinerTheHumanEcologyofMusic.pd f Glidden, R. (2007). Response to B ennett R eimer's "why do humans value music?" Retrieved December 2, 2009, from http://www.menc.org/documents/onlinepublications/ vision2020/ResponsetoReim er.pdf Gonzo, C. (1993). Multicultural issues in music education. Music Educators Journal, 79, 49 52. Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education 2(2). Available at http://act.maydaygroup.org/articles/Green2_2.pdf Green, M. (1988). The dialectic of freedom. New York: Teachers College Press. Haack, S. (1998). Manifesto of a passionate moderate. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

PAGE 126

120 Hanslick, E. (1957). Th e beautiful in music (G. Cohen, Trans.). Indianapolis: The Liberal Arts Press. Hargreaves, D. J., & Marshall, N. A. (2003). Developing identities in music education. Music Education Research, 5 (3), 263 274. Hargreaves, D. J., & North, A. C. (2007). Lifesty le correlates of musical preference. Psychology of Music, 35, 179 200. Harvey, D. (1989). The condition of postmodernity: And inquiry into the origins of cultural change. Oxford, UK: Blackwell Publishing. Hennoin, A. (2001). Music lovers: Taste as performa nce. Theory, Culture & Society Hooks, B. (1994). Teaching to transgress. education as the practice of freedom. New York: Routledge. Horkheimer, M., & Adorno, T. W. (2002). Dialectic of enlightenment (G. S. Noerr, Ed.) (E. Jephcott, Trans.). St anford, California: Stanford University Press. IES ( 2009). National Center for Educational Statistics. Retrieved February 15 th 2010 from http://nces.ed.gov/fastfacts/display.asp?id=372 Jaffurs, S. (2004). Developing musicality: Formal and informal practic es. Action, Criticism, and Theory for Music Education, 3 (3). Jorgensen, E. (1991). On philosophical method. In R. Colwell (Ed.), Handbook of research in music education (pp. 91 101). New York: Shirmer. Jorgensen, E. (1996). Justifying music in general educ ation: Belief in search of reason. Philosophy of Education. Retrieved November 4, 2008, from http://www.ed.uiuc.edu/EPS/PES Yearbook/96_docs/jorgensen.html

PAGE 127

121 Jorgensen, E. (1997). In search of music education. Urbana: University of Illinois Press. Jorgensen, E. (2003). Western classical music and general education. Philosophy of Music Education Review, 11 (2), 130 140. Journo, E. (2004). Multiculturalism's war on education. In Bucks County Courier Times Retrieved April 2nd, 2008, from http://www.ayn rand.org/site/News2?page=NewsArt icle&id=10249&news_iv_ctrl =1021 Kim, J. Y., & Belkin, N. J. (2002). Categories of music description and search terms and phrases used by non music experts Retrieved December 2, 2009, from http://ismir2002.ismi r.net/proceedi ngs/02 FP07 2.pdf Kivy, P. (1990). Music alone. Ithica and London: Cornell University Press. Kivy, P. (2002). Introduction to a philosophy of music. New York: Oxford University Press. Koza, J. E. (1996). Multicultural approaches to music education. In C. A Grand & M. L. Gomez (Eds.), Making schooling multicultural: Campus and classroom (pp. 263 287). Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall. Krannawitter, T. L. (2003). The intellectual errors and political dangers of multiculturalism (Debate Transcript). Retrie ved April 18th, 2008, from http://www.claremont.org/publi cations/pub/print.asp?pubid=480 Locke, E. (2002). On flag day celebrate America's core values: Reason, rights, and science. Impact (supplimental). Retrieved April 1st, 2008, from http://www.claremont. org/publications/p ub/print.asp?pubid=480

PAGE 128

122 Mark, M. L., & Gary, C. L. (1999). A history of american music education. Reston, VA: MENC, The National Association for Music Education. McCarthy, M. (2004). Toward a global community: The internation society for music education. British Journal of Music Education, 21, 349 351. McLaren, P. (1994). White terror and oppositional agency: Towards a critical multiculturalism. In D. T. Goldberg (Ed.), Multiculturalism: A critical reader (pp. e, MA: Blackwell. McGowan, J. (1991). Postmodernism and its critics. Ithica: Cornell University Press. Miralis, Y. (2002). Multicultural world music education and music teacher education at the big ten schools: Identified problems and suggestions (Doctoral dissertation, Michigan State University). Dissertation Abstracts International, 54 (08), 2142A. Miralis, Y. (2006). Clarifying the terms "multicultural," "multiethnic," and "world music education" through a review of literature. Update: Applications of Res earch in Music Education, 24 (2), 54 67. Lundquist, B. Szego, C. K. w. N. B., Santos R. & and Solbu, E. Eds. (1998). Musics of the world's cultures: A source book for music educators. Nedlands, W. A.: Callaway International Resource Centre for Music Educati on (CIRCME) for the International Society for Music Education (ISME). Norman, K. N. (1994). Multicultural music education: Perceptions of current and prospective music education faculty, music supervisors, and music teachers (Doctoral dissertation, University of Michigan). Dissertation Abstracts International, 56 (01), 0131A.

PAGE 129

123 Olsson, B. (2007). A classic updated: A review essay. International Journal of Education & the Arts, 8 (1), 1 11. Retrieved November 1, 2008, from http://ijea.asu.edu/v8r1. Peter son, R. A., & Kern, R. M. (1996). Changing highbrow taste: From snob to omnivore. American Sociological Review, 61 (5), 900 907. Phillips, K. H. (2004). Directing the choral music program. Oxford University Press, New York, NY. Razack, S. H. (2006). Looking white people in the eye: Gender, race and culture in courtrooms and classrooms. Toronto: University of Toronto Press. Regelski, T. A. (2005). Music and music education: Theory and praxis for 'making a difference.' Educational Philosophy and Theory, 37 (1), 7 27. Reimer, B. (2005). A philosophy of music education: Advancing the vision, 3rd edition. New Jersey: Prentice Hall. Reimer, B. (2007). Comprehensive education, comprehensive music education Online journal article available at meri.arts.usf.edu. MERI Volume 1, 2007. Reiner, R. (Director) (1987). The Princess Bride [Motion picture] United States: 20 th Century Fox. Rossenau, P. M. (1992). Postmodernism and the social sciences: Insights, inroads, and intrusions. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Schwarts, P. (2002). Back to the dark ages: Today's attacks on reason, individualism and progress. Impact (supplimental). Retrieved April 1st, 2008, from http://aynrand.org/site/DocSeerver/newsletter_ multiculturalism.pdf?dociID=162 Simon, H. A. (1977). Mode ls of discovery and other topics in the method of science. Dordrecht, Netherlands: D. Reidel; Pallas paperback.

PAGE 130

124 Sloboda, J. (2001). Conference keynote: Emotion, functionality and the everyday experience of music: Where does music education fit? Music Educa tion Research, 37 (2), 243 253. Small, C. (1996). Music, society, education. New England, Hanover, and London: Wesleyan University Press. Small, C. (1998). Musicking Middletown, CT, Wesleyan University Press Small, C. (1989). Music of the common tongue: Survival and celebration in A A merican music. London, Wesleyan University Press. Smith, R. A. (2006). Culture and the arts in education: Critical essays on shaping human experience. New York: Teacher College Press and the National Art Education Association. Sokal, A. (1996). Transgressing the boundaries: Towards a transformative hermeneutics of quantum gravity. Social Text, 46/47 (spring/summer), 217 252. Spelman, E. (1988). Inessential woman: Problems of excl usion in feminist thought. Boston: Beacon Press. Tiedt, P. L., & Tiedt, I. M. (1995). Multicultural teaching: A handbook of activities, information and resources (4th edition). Boston: Allyn & Bacon. Tolbert, E. ( 2001) Music and Meaning: An Evolutionary S tory. Psychology of Music Turner, S. (2009). The future of social theory. In B. Turner (Ed.), The new B lackwell companion to social theory (pp. 551 566). London, New York: Blackwell Publishing.

PAGE 131

125 Turner, S. (1989). Truth and Decision. Science of the pedestal: Social perspectives on science and technology. Chubin, D. E., and Chu, E. W., eds. Wadsworth, UNESCO. (2005). Convention of the protection and promotion of the diversity of cultural expressions. In The general conference of the United Nations Educational, Scientific and Cultural Organization in Paris Retrieved April 1st, 2008, from http://unesdoc.unesco.org/images/0014/001429/142919e.pdf Usher, R., & Edwards, R. (1994). Postmodernism and education. London: Rout ledge. Vaugeois, L. (2007). Social justice and music eduction: Claiming the space of music education as a site of postcolonial contestation. Action, Criticism, and Theiry for Music Education, 6 (4). Retrieved April 1st, 2008, from http://act.maydaygro up.org /articles/Vaugeois6_4.pdf Volk, T. M. (1997). Music, education, and multiculturalism: Foundations and principles. New York: Oxford University Press. Westerlund, H. (2003). Reconsidering aesthetic experience in praxial music education. Philosophy of Music E ducation Review, 11 (1), 45 62. Williams, D. (2007). What are music educators doing and how well are we doing it. Music Educators Journal, 94 (1), 18 23

PAGE 132

About the Author rkansas University in 1995. He taught secondary choral music for five years before becoming the Director of Choral Activities at Florida College in 2001. In 2006, Mr. Bassett began the Ph.D. program at the University of South Florida. He continues to teach as a full time professor at Florida College and as an adjunct professor at the University of South Florida. Mr. Bassett resides in Tampa with his wife Jenny and their three children.